Epilogue
The future of man
remains undetermined because it depends on him.
Henri Bergson
We propose here to
take three critical steps back,
through institutions, which we have been discussing most recently, and
authority, which we dealt with before that, to the individual. We shall
see
that as we take these steps, we sink in turgescence, redundance and
hypocrisy,
which reveal human realities beyond either biological or philosophical
circumscriptions. Our discussion is not intended to be a summation of
what the
book has covered, but some afterthoughts on the nature of the phenomena
considered.
I. Institutional
Turgescence
In the context of the
total environment, men and their
social, and political institutions should make sense, not necessarily
in any
ultimate terms, but at least in relation to each other. However, these
relationships‑‑and this must be emphasized‑‑take place
in the context of the total environment. When we observe, for example,
the
existence of an institution, we may infer a corresponding need. On
closer
examination we may find that the institution does not correspond to the
need,
or that the need does not exist. But that is only because we have
looked
closely‑‑too closely, perhaps, If we broaden our perspective, we
may find that while, according to certain rationale, the institution in
question may not correspond to a given need, we can nevertheless
explain its
existence. In an underdeveloped country a few years ago, I visited a
village
which had traffic lights but practically no motor vehicle traffic. The
institution obviously did not have a corresponding need, That is true,
however,
only if we forget the human element. There were traffic lights in the
otherwise
underdeveloped village because, in the first place, the region had an
excess of
electricity due to the construction of a new dam and because traffic
lights, if
they did not serve as useful signs,
at least served as symbols of
progress, modernity and therefore prestige. Of course, in general, we
are
probably more likely to find intersections that need traffic lights but
don't
have them, or traffic lights that are not properly synchronized and
thus
contribute to traffic jams rather than alleviate them. The example of
the
traffic light is rather simplistic. The point is that institutions do
not
always correspond to needs in the social‑rationale sense.
By institutions we
mean any aspect of cognizable social
and political structures ‑‑ whether moral, ethical or legal norms,
or constituted bodies such as an association or an office. Our earlier
causal
assumption that an institution implied a need for it was itself
indicative of
the need/institution lag. It
implied that in human terms an
institution is created to fulfill a need, which further implied the
likelihood
that the need preceded the institution. This is plausible considering
man's
attributes as a thinking animal whose institutions do not result simply
from
spontaneous and automatic instincts. He may create institutions in
anticipation
of future needs; but they will not necessarily correspond to needs once
they
arise; for while man can predict, he
cannot know the future in the
complexity of the total environment. The mention of the total
environment
should remind us again that it is not enough to explain the
need/institution
lag on the basis of rational rationales but also in the light of human,
and not
always so rational, factors. Need X may
arise at point x. Not only will
institution Y not come about
spontaneously, but it may not even be provided at point x'
when the need for it has been identified. Depending on the
circumstances, institution Y may
never be created.
Fig. E‑01
There may be other
priorities pre‑empting the
provision of institution Y for need X.
That is, the need for the institution
may be felt by those who need it, but not recognized by those who
establish the
institutions.
By the same token,
because of the discrepancy between
those in need and the institution‑makers, even when an institution is
created to meet a particular need, a gap
will exist between the intrinsic need factor and its extrinsic
evaluation and
satisfaction by the institution. Here, of course, we are implying all
the
complexities covered throughout the book, such as the degree of
participation
and control which those who need an institution have in creating and
running
it. The more those who run the institution coincide with those who need
it and
the more they are controllable and accountable for the utility and
efficiency
of the institutions, the smaller the gap between the need and the
institution. But
in human terms, it is hard to conceive that they will totally coincide.
Indeed,
if they did they would consummate each other,
and the need/institution constellation would hardly be
recognizable. So,
even if institution Y were created to
satisfy need X at point x' when the
need for the institution was
identified, Y should not be presented
as superimposed on the trend of X,
but placed at a gap with it. The gap will be wider or narrower,
depending on
the coincidence of the identity and understanding of those in need and
those in
charge of the institution.
Fig. E‑02
But a gap, no matter
how narrow, will always exist. Even
an individual does not always provide means ‑‑ even when he can and
is consciously aware of them -‑ to satisfy his own needs. The social
need/institution gap can, of course, increase or decrease where there
are
deviations and adaptations ‑‑ which may be mutual, because needs
can also be conditioned by existing institutions. Also, it is possible
that
those instrumental in creating an institution may cause it to cease
functioning
before the need has been met, in which case there will again be a lag
further
along the need/institution combination representing an unsatisfied
need. This
last hypothesis, however, demands another reminder of human and social
conditions. A partially satisfied need is harder to suppress than one
that has
not been acknowledged at all, because a human institution is not like
running
water or electricity that can readily be turned on and off. Beyond its
implication that those whose needs the institution served will be more
consciously dissatisfied, the phenomenon leads us, in our broad
perspective, to
another human dimension central to our present inquiry.
By virtue of their
human factors, human institutions are
not simply organic and mechanical. A human institution not only serves
a social
purpose and a need, but is at the same time an instrument for those who
control
it, and a source of livelihood for those who maintain it. An
institution,
therefore, evolves not only according to the social need for which it
is
supposed to have been created, but also under the influence of its
controllers
and occupants.
It is understandable
that those who control an
institution cherish it as a base of their power, and it is equally
understandable
that those whose livelihood depends on the institution also want to
perpetuate
it. While the evolution of an institution for such reasons can be
explained
within the rationale of the total environment, it is not always easily
justifiable within the narrower relational rationale of the original
social
need which it was presumably created to satisfy. We may call the lag
resulting
from that evolution institutional
turgescence. Not only may it cause
the institutional trend to deviate from that of the need, but it may
also
perpetuate the institution beyond the need. For example, those who
control the
institution ‑‑ at different levels of responsibility ‑‑
will probably try to consolidate the base of their power by populating
the
institution with their own types, a trend that can result in
favoritism,
nepotism and the spoils system. Institutional turgescence is also
reflected in
the bureaucratic propensity to create busywork, redtape and extra
positions to
handle it, expanding the institution into a self‑perpetuating and
self‑propelling
body. Parkinson's Law did not gain renown as a satire because it was
merely
amusing, but because it depicted a human reality ‑‑ and not a new
one. Chaucer, six centuries earlier,
had said of his Sergent of the Law:
Nowhere
was there a man as busy
as he‑
And yet
he seemed busier than he
was.
Institutional
turgescence develops more easily when the
institution is fed funds indirectly so that the connection between the
funds
invested and the institution's corresponding accomplishments are
blurred, and
when there are fewer checks and balances, whether directly by those
whose
social needs the institution serves or by other institutions. The
citizen is
more likely to notice his mayor using for private ends the limousine
bought
with public money for official business than he is to notice his
country's
ambassadors in other lands doing
so.
For purposes of
analyzing a polity's efficacy, we can
establish an institutional turgescence scale. Where the lag between the
emergence of needs, their recognition, and the creation of institutions
to
satisfy them is short; where the gap between needs and institutions
remains
narrow; and where the lag between the passing away of a need and the
dismantling of the corresponding institution is short, the polity may
be
considered harmonious and stable, with small zones of conflict and
dissatisfaction. Where these conditions are reversed the likelihood of
conflict
increases. Whether the greater zones of conflict between the needs and
institutions will cause the polity to collapse depends on the
consciousness of
those involved. For those in the institutional oligarchy, the situation
may
sometimes look more and more like it is working because they have shut
out
their critical vision. Yet the situation may continue if those in need
are
resigned to the prevailing order. In other words,
there are psychological factors involved which could either
help perpetuate the establishment or precipitate change.
II. Authority
Redundance
When in Chapter Two we
defined liberty as a sociological
need, we used an elementary proposition to explain that, abstractly
speaking,
man lives in groups because, all considered, they are better than the
state of
nature. Formally, the proposition could read: GB > SN (i.e., Group Benefits
are greater than what man can get in the State of Nature). We have long established that because man is a
political
animal, the state of nature has never been a human reality. But even
though man
is caught in his social dimension, he dreams of and visualizes a
wilderness
where he could speak his mind to the authorities who push him around.
This idea
was reflected in some of our topics, such as those dealing with man's
adventurer inclinations and with anti‑norms. Now, with all the
complexities we have behind us, let us use our simple formula in a
simple
hypothesis of polity development to see whether there is any inherent
human
phenomenon keeping institutions from corresponding totally to social
needs.
By "group," we said,
we did not mean a cluster
of units confining each other but interacting with one another. To put
it more
concretely, in a small communal setting, Mr. Jones, wanting to contact
Mr.
Smith ‑‑ to go to his farm, for example ‑‑ would have
to go through Mr. Doe's domain – Doe’s place of sustenance and rest.
This
intrusion of Doe's domain ‑‑ his liberty ‑‑ is, part of
the price he pays for the benefits he draws from the group. In fact,
Jones'
passing through may be no intrusion at all. Doe may enjoy having the
chance to
chat with Jones. That can be part of the group benefits. If, however,
the group
grows so that more and more people whom Doe knows less and less keep
passing
through his domain, it might become a nuisance for him and for others
who
submit to the same interference. The practice could, in effect,
establish a
right of passage through their domains and thus infringe on their
rights,
giving rise to the need for a public road.
We can, of course,
conceive of an already existing
authority to take charge of satisfying this need. But to make our point
step by
step, let us assume that to take care of the need for a public road,
the
members of the group join to establish a particular authority. First,
of
course, they have to decide where the road should be, which may imply
that some
have to cede their land and that others have to compensate them. We are
slowly
moving beyond the informal group benefits toward more explicit and
formal
public interests, which call for further concessions by individual
members of
the group, including remuneration for the authority established to
build roads.
In our hypothesis of the individual's conscious participation in group
life and
his hypothetical alternative, the state of nature, we should now add
the new
dimension of public interests to our
formula. The sum total of the group benefits and the advantages to be
drawn
from public interests (PuI) should be
greater than the concessions one makes on his hypothetical absolute
freedom of
action in the state of nature. Thus:
|GB + PuI| > SN.
Of course, public
interests refer not only to a single
situation such as constructing a means of communication. Any society
beyond an
isolated primeval level develops social needs for intercourse and
exchange
requiring structures and rules, i.e., institutions and laws. Beyond a
certain
group size, authority cannot be exercised by the whole aggregate of
individual
members and will have to be vested in some body (individual or
institution)
responsible for organizing the institutions which serve public
interests. It
will speak in the name of the group which has instituted it. Let us
designate
this authority as A. A
will become the concrete representation of the abstract "group," a
point of reference for both its individual members and those who serve
the
group.
If, in our example of
road‑building, someone finds
the road not properly constructed, he will complain to A.
In like manner the contractor building the road, recognizing A as the job‑giver, will heed his
instructions and pay him due respect. The concentration of the group's
"will"
in authority A and the exercise of
his assigned functions thus acquire for A
a certain amount of prestige and an aura of superiority by which he may
be
advantaged and on which he may draw beyond the quid pro
quo remuneration of his services. The road contractor may
do a better job around A's property
for which, in the long run, the other members of the society will pay.
The city
mayor may receive more respect and consideration from the police corps
than
does the common citizen. Try to tell the tax collector or the policeman
that
you contribute to his upkeep and that he is really your servant; you
will be in
trouble! The president of the republic is honored: traffic is stopped
for him
and he is accompanied by a motorcade.
As authority becomes
more complex, some of these
additional attributes which do not directly contribute to public
interests are
conceded by the members of the group, and others are taken, or taken
for
granted, by the authority. While the remuneration A receives
for his
services may be considered an expense incurred for the sake of public
interest,
the surplus attributes he accumulates because of his position entail no
returns
for the group members, who put up with them as necessary evils for the
sake of
the GB and the PuI. In our formula,
it should be deducted from their total. Let us
call these surplus attributes Authority
Redundance (AR):
|GB + PuI ‑ AR|> SN.
Authority redundance
cannot be calculated objectively. It
is a psychological factor and, in the final analysis, depends on what
the
individual considers redundant. Some authority attributes may engender
affectional satisfactions, such as national pride in a coronation, a
military
parade or a monument. They cannot altogether be considered authority
redundance, for they contribute to group benefits and public interests
by
nurturing such strongholds as nationalism and cultural identity, which
provide
group cohesion.
Up to now our formula
has confined the individual's side
to the hypothetical state of nature alternative. We pointed out earlier
that,
while the individual may indulge in weighing the advantages of social
life
against those of the state of nature, the state of nature is only a
point of
reference, like the North Star for navigators, and not a state the
individual
can attain totally. As the formula now stands, group life is a
take‑it‑or‑leave‑it
proposition for the individual, with the "leave‑it" side only
hypothetical. But this situation would reduce the individual to
servitude. In
the extreme he would be a slave in chains. Beyond that extreme,
however, social
dynamics assume an exchange between the two sides of the formula. The
state‑of‑nature
freedom, which the individual relinquishes and which turns into group
benefits,
public interests and authority redundance on the other side of the
formula, is
the raw material on which the group draws, but which also, as
individual
liberty, emanates from the group as a whole, of which the individual is
a part.
Thus he can aspire to share in the social part of the formula. In other
words,
the individual has some potential power (PP)
which, socially speaking, he can at
some stage convert into social action. The more the conversion of
potential
power is fluid, the more the individual not only enjoys the fruits of
group and
public action, but also partakes in shaping them, and consequently either shares authority
redundance or neutralizes it. We may now realize that when the
conversion of
this potential power of the individual to the |GB + PuI – AR| side is handicapped, his
alternative
is not reduced to the hypothetical abandonment of social life,
reverting to the
state of nature. His potential power may turn instead into Militancy
Potentials (MP)
within the social context to resist and fight what may have become an
unacceptable amount of authority redundance. Our formula will then read:
|GB + PuI – AR| > |SN + MP|
←PP---
The establishment
maintains itself best where the members
of the society, like Voltaire's Candide, believe that "all is well in
the
best of all possible worlds." This situation does not necessarily imply
the greatest social consensus, public service, flexibility and mobility
among
the social strata, but may imply high degrees of conformity, strict
socialization, persuasion and indoctrination, as discussed earlier. The
harmonious
consensual situation is, of course, one where maximum group benefits
and public
advantages are enjoyed by the members of society, where authorities do
not
abuse their positions, and where the process for converting individual
potentials into social benefits is adequate. These advantages need not
all be
present for the establishment to survive. For example, while some
members may
consider that at a given time the advantages offered by the
establishment are
not satisfactory and the authority's abuse of power is excessive, they
will not
necessarily use their militancy potentials to overthrow the
establishment, but
may rely on the future conversion of their potential power to replace
the
established authority. Such would be the case of an opposition
political party
in a polity that provides for an honest electoral process.
Our conceptual
formulation should therefore be understood
as a temporal continuum, and our power potentials as those potentials
which,
under the existing social order, are convertible at a future time.
Potentials
converted immediately become militancy potentials, amounting to a
revolt
against the establishment. The student who disagrees with the
educational
system as provided by the establishment may yet submit to it because it
offers him
possibilities to play a role in the establishment in the future. After
he has
obtained his degree, whatever social benefits he draws from it will be
transferred to his social side of the formula, and he will rethink his
formula
in the light of his new position and power potentials. The student who
does not
believe the system is worthwhile may revolt, either by violence or by
alienation, by joining a militant body or a commune. The final outcome
of this
on the social structure will depend on the dynamics of the dissatisfied
elements and their impact.
A situation is, of
course, conceivable in which the
establishment side of the formula is negative and yet the establishment
maintains itself. This would correspond to a despotic police state
where
authority redundance exceeds the benefits offered to the members of the
society. Authority redundance includes not only the money the dictator
spends
on his limousines, but also the police force he maintains which does
not
safeguard the members of society but persecutes them, puts them in jail
and
encroaches on their liberties. Somoza’s crushing of the uprising in
Nicaragua
in 1978 was a classic example. In such a
situation, AR > |SN + MP|;
i.e., the individuals or groups submit to the establishment, although
resenting
it, because they have too few liberties and militancy potentials to
reverse the
trend of authority redundance. If and when the trend can be reversed
and a
successful attempt is made, it will be revolutionary instead of the
previously
discussed evolutionary conversion of
power potentials. Anarchy, in the popular sense of nonexistence
of government and consequent confusion
and disorganization, may accompany the moment of passage when AR = |SN + MP|, and may
last
longer where the SN factor within the
emerging powers is greater, or shorter where the MP
prevails (militancy also implying discipline). As with the
revolution the potentials materialize into the establishment, the
members of
society will become entangled in the new social network with its new
authority
redundance. The subjective evaluation of social realities by
individuals,
whether those who constitute (or feel they constitute) the
establishment or
those who submit to it, and their corresponding behavior and actions
are then
the raw material of political authority. Thus, after our brief and
critical
second look at institutions and authority, our final step takes us back
to the
individual human behavior with which we began.
III. The
Ideal/Real/Hypocritical Loop
At the beginning of
this book we said that political
science was the science of truth. We know, however, that truth is
relative,
depending very much on what an individual believes to be true. To the
extent
that he acts thereupon, his truth becomes the convictional support for
his
action. Truth, however, is relative not only to the individual but also
to his
total environment. In the social context, truth according to a man's
belief and
the actual social phenomena is hard to perceive and to establish. The
possible
range for an individual oscillates between two extremes: the ideal and the hypocritical.
He may base
his truth on abstract values, and his "untruth" on his selfish
interests; i.e., he may be an idealist in the application of his truth
to his
social realities, or be a hypocrite in their evaluation for his
personal needs.
In the latter case, his values are false values, as elaborated earlier.
Politics is said to be
the art of the possible because it
requires consciousness of the critical
limits of social realities between the ideal and hypocritical extremes.
Politics is an art, however, not only because it requires consciousness
of the
limits and the extremes, but also because it calls for courage and
potentials
for probing those limits yet not falling into the extremes. Indeed, it
is critically
probing the limits that gives the political practitioner or scientist
the broad
perspective he needs of the social realities he is to cope with. The
political
practitioner or scientist who confines himself to the strictly material
and
concrete factors of social reality narrows his angle of vision. By
approaching
the ideal limits of social realities, he will enlarge his vision and
understanding of the "valuational" improvements that are
possible within the social context
he deals with. But he can do so only by moving, on the other side, to
the brink
of hypocrisy within the social realities in order to know the real
stuff of the
society, the visceral contents of the man he is dealing with.
You will see now why
the real art of politics is so
difficult to master, for it is very difficult to understand the
possible limits
of the ideal without becoming an impractical idealist, and it is
equally
difficult to use one's power to the limits of the hypocritical in order
to
understand the egoistic interests of others, and to promote one's
political
cause for social good, without
falling into the excesses of self‑indulgence. While by probing the ideal and the hypocritical limits of
social realities critically the political practitioner or scientist
broadens
his angle of vision, at the two extremes he also risks to sink into the
ideal
nebula or the hypocritical viscera. That could narrow his angle of
vision until
he is totally submerged. He may then become vulnerable, taking his
ideal or
hypocritical vision as real, and may indeed take one for the other to
justify
and balance, consciously or unconsciously, his behavior and action
within the
social environment. By rationalizing instead of being rational, he
would make
the two extremes meet and thus produce for himself an
ideal/real/hypocritical
loop where the ideal/hypocritical side mirrors the real, as the
negative
mirrors the photograph.
Within that loop,
hypocritical actions may be justified
by ideal abstractions, and selfish interests may wear a mask of
altruism. In
the name of civilization the British massacred the Mau Mau and the
French
tried to suppress the Algerian uprising; in the name of
anti‑imperialism
the Russians suppressed the Hungarian revolt and invaded
Czechoslovakia; and in
the name of anticommunism the Americans carpet‑bombed Hanoi. These are
generally known international issues. But if we look into our own
immediate
political and social surroundings, we are bound to trace back to the
ideal/hypocritical loop, to different degrees at different levels,
whatever
turgescence in the institutions and redundance in the authorities we
may find.
It is, indeed, by confounding ideals with hypocrisy that "the people"
claim citizenship in a democracy without participating in its political
process. And when they do participate, rationalizing their private
interests
into public good, they let interest groups manipulate and control the
political
process and institutions, helping politicians and bureaucrats create
their own
ideal/hypocritical loop.
The "ideal" solution,
keeping in mind all the
socio‑political complexities covered, is political
consciousness and participation on the part of every member
of the society beyond private interests. But that is an ideal which
can be
strived for only if we look closer into ourselves and observe how
often, when
our interests are not at stake, we float on the clouds of idealism, and
how,
when it comes to our precious selves, we descend into the thick of
hypocrisy.
We are the stuff of which politics is made: to understand politics, we
must
first know men, and that is ourselves. Knowledge of the problem is part
of the
solution.