Chapter
14
People
and Government
Quod omnes
tangit ab omnibus approbatur.[1]
Writ
of Summons to the
British
Model
Parliament of
1295
Democracy, in its
original
connotation, means rule by the people. Like all other political terms,
however,
it should not be taken at face value. How do the people rule? Even
where people
can assemble in the marketplace and deliberate on the affairs of the
polis, as
they did in the Greek city-states, perennial questions arise as to the
number
and qualifications of "the people." The Greek city-state was a
democracy for the freemen. The slaves were not part of "the people,"
nor did the women and children take part in political deliberations.
These
facts already reduced "the people" to a minority (about 40,000 out of
a population of some 300,000). Such restrictions were the norm for
political
participation up to modern times, and in some places still are.
What justifies these
restrictions? One who discriminates against women or slaves might
question
whether "people" implies a simple count of bodies, and if so whether
new-born children are also entitled to vote. The argument may sound
ridiculous
because it is drawn ad absurdum. But
it becomes a valid concern as we move toward more fluid situations.
Indeed, if
it is ridiculous to inquire whether new-born children should vote, it
is not at
all absurd to inquire at what age a person should be considered mature
enough
to participate in political deliberations and what the criteria for
maturity
are. The answer, of course, is: It all depends. Life experience,
education, the
age at which a culture makes adult demands on the individual are among
the
determining factors. If, before a certain age, individuals are
considered unfit
for decision-making in public and political affairs, there must be
certain
standards to measure such fitness. These standards developed as
traditional
cultures observed symptoms of maturity and immaturity over long periods
of
time. If the symptoms classified as immature in terms of youth were
detected in
other social and human categories, members of those categories were
also
considered unfit for political decision-making. In the traditional
settings,
such symptoms were seen (in different degrees) in full grown slaves and
women.
The logical conclusion, then, was that slaves and women were
biologically
handicapped to participate in the political process because, even when
grown
up, they were less mature than the emancipated freemen. The indexes may
have
been very slight, but they suggested underdevelopment.
But not fully taken
into
account was the socialization factor and the handicaps of slaves and
women due
to their social positions and expected roles. Even modern quantitative
measurements point to the traditional prejudices and "confirm what
poets
and novelists have often asserted, and the average layman long
believed,
namely, that men not only behave but 'think' differently from women."[2] David Wechsler's study of 850 male and 850
female subjects showed slight discrepancies in favor of men in matters
requiring reasoning and judgment, while women had a slight edge over
men in
areas relating to memory or imitative aptitudes. As for slavery we must
bear in
mind that it did not always coincide with race but rather with the
social class
of instrumentality, subservience and dispossession; and the two, race
and lack
of property, remained handicaps for political disenfranchisement up to
modern
times in many political cultures.
I.
Representation
Beyond possible
restrictions on
the basis of age, sex, race and property (or class), the idea of
democracy
engenders a numeric paradox, as it is unlikely that all the people will
agree
with each other all the time on how to rule. The ideal of democracy
could
probably be unanimity; then nearest to it, consensus. But in a
heterogeneous society
decisions are likely to be made by a majority or even a plurality of
those who
bother to vote. Further, there are organizational factors qualifying a
democracy. In the first place, the matter being deliberated by "the
people" must be formulated, then executed. Second, if a political
culture
grows beyond a certain size, it will not be possible to assemble all
its
people, and delegates or representatives will have to deliberate in
their
behalf.
Electoral
Arrangements
This numeric paradox
has
inspired the multitude of electoral systems adopted by different
countries.
These systems and voting processes draw their rationale from the
realities of
political cultures. There seems to be no universally "just" and
foolproof system for all times and places. The degree to which an
electoral
system accommodates the two basic concerns of popular
participation and effective
government makes it appropriate for a given polity. Whether the
system is
effective and reasonable depends on the issues being decided, who is
finally
omitted from deciding them, whether those left out trust those inside,
and
whether those left out have real chances of eventually getting in. Let
us look
at some electoral rationales.
Where the electorate
is
homogeneous, where the issues are not valuationally controversial but
have
alternate modes of implementation, and where no matter who wins a
general trust
prevails among the voters, even a plurality system can suffice.
Plurality
implies that among more than two alternatives, whoever or whichever
rallies the
most votes will win, although not necessarily receiving a majority.
Plurality
is adopted as an electoral process even where the criteria of
homogeneity and
valuational consensus are not altogether met, such as in the
parliamentary
elections in Great Britain, Canada and the United States. Because
plurality has
the possible advantage of being expeditious and comparatively simple. In 1968, Richard Nixon was elected president
of the United States by slightly over one-fourth of the estimated
voting-age
population (31,785,480 votes out of an estimate of 120,006,000 eligible
to
vote).
In a heterogeneous
society with
diverse values and interests, does a voting process which in effect
legitimizes
an authority based on a minority satisfy the ideal of government of the
people,
by the people, for the people? Rousseau addressed his principle of the
"general will" to this concern of not having a particular class or
interest group minority take hold of the government. By basing
political
deliberations on the vote of the majority, the will of the people was
legitimized into the general will. His criterion was that as
sovereignty rested
with "the people," their "weightier part" (numerically)
would be the appropriate legitimizing body. Ever since the French
Revolution
many voting processes have been inspired by this majority
rule. Where there are only two alternatives, there will
generally be a majority winner (unless there is a tie which, especially
in the
case of popular elections, is hardly probable). With more than two
contestants,
none may win a majority on the first ballot, in which case a second
ballot is
needed. The second ballot can be arranged in different combinations.
Majority
rule can be waived in favor of plurality, where those whose candidate
or issue
does not seem to have a chance of winning are ideologically disposed to
opt for
a viable alternative nearest to their values and interests. Or, to
insure more
effective government, those not having achieved a certain percentage
may be
eliminated and the second ballot reduced to a few major contestants. Or
only
the two contestants with the largest plurality may be left to compete
for a
majority on the second ballot, as is the case in French presidential
elections
under the Fifth Republic. All these combinations reflect the social
philosophy
that there can be a second choice of ideology and values, and a
compromise of
interests.
The plurality and
majority
rules so far examined have been presented in a single-member-district
context; that is, there is one outcome once
voting is completed. But certain ideologies, values and interests in a
heterogeneous society may not always find grounds for compromise, and
if the
final single outcome is based on a majority, by definition excluding
the
minority from control of the authority, there may arise the possibility
of the
tyranny of the majority. To alleviate this undemocratic shortcoming of
single-member districts, electoral systems have been devised to provide
for proportional representation. There are
many such schemes. The basic social philosophy behind them is to permit
a fair
representation of different views, ideologies and interests. The system
may be
limitative in that it may require the parties participating in the
elections to
gather a minimum percentage of the votes to qualify for representation.
The
limitation may be inspired either by a desire to reduce dispersion of
tendencies in the representative body and provide some degree of
effectiveness
in government, or by the conspiracy of a polity's prominent interests
to keep
smaller and less palatable ideologies out of the political process.
Some
proportional representation systems are cumulative,
permitting transfer and accumulation of votes across electoral
districts so
that even if a party has not mustered enough votes in any electoral
district it
may eventually be represented. The cumulative system can also be
combined with
the minimum percentage requirement at the national level to secure, as
much as
possible, fair representation of the social currents without letting
the
representative body be handicapped by excessive fragmentation.
The transfer of votes
in the
cumulative system requires their grouping in recognizable categories
and
ideological labels beyond individual votes for individual candidates.
This can
lead to a list system in which
political parties present a list of their candidates to the electorate,
which
then chooses parties rather than candidates. The voter is thus further
removed
from the representational process unless he is actively engaged in
party
politics. In some electoral systems, such as those of Belgium and the
Netherlands, the voters, while voting for a party list, can also
indicate their
preference for given candidates on the list. Thus, when the votes are
counted
and each party allocated its seats, those seats will go to candidates
who
gathered more votes. Proportional representation, mentioned in Chapter
Twelve
as Mill's favorite but which has been found too complicated for
practical
purposes (or maybe, as Mill said, too favorable to elite participation
in the
political process) was the electoral system proposed by Thomas Hare in
1859. It
provided for single transferable votes
and personal representation. To be
elected a candidate needed a minimum quota of ballots calculated on the
basis
of the electoral votes divided by the number of seats. The candidates
could
present themselves or be nominated individually, and the voters would
not be
limited to the candidates in their own district but could vote on all
candidates in the country. They could list candidates in order of
preference so
that if their first choice had already received the number of votes
established
by the quota for election, the elector's votes could be counted towards
their
next choice. In this system the concern to make popular participation a
flexible reality and the expectation of popular consciousness about the
political process are very high. The fact remains, however, that
whether it is
simple plurality in a single=member district system, or cumulative
proportional
representation, their two intertwined concerns are: legitimizing
authority
through popular participation and making effective government possible.
The two
are compatible only to the extent that the electoral process has
managed to
turn "the people" into their socio-political realization--"the
public."
The
People and The Public
"People," as a
political term, has the massive connotation of the body politic in a
democracy.
It is derived from the Latin word populus.
No hairsplitting is intended, but a look into the origins of these
words will
help us understand some of their political implications. Populus
in Latin also means a poplar (tree), probably because the
masses resemble its multitude of leaves wavering in the wind. Another
derivation of the word means plunder! "Public," on the other hand, is
derived from the Latin word pubes,
which means of ripe age; "puberty" is also derived from the same
root. Democracy as the rule of the people will become a republic when,
instead
of rule by the masses of the people, the lawful body of their
representatives
exercises the business of government on their behalf. Madison
distinguished
between the two by saying that "in a democracy, the people meet and
exercise the government in person" while "in a republic, they
assemble and administer it by their representatives and agents."[3] The distinction, however, is not made only
for organizational convenience, as a means to circumvent the
impossibility of
massive assembly, but also for valuational considerations, which we
need to record
here for later discussions; and for that, we shall further quote
Madison:
The two
great points of difference between a democracy and a republic are:
first, the
delegation of the government, in the latter, to a small number of
citizens
elected by the rest; secondly, the greater number of citizens, and
greater
sphere of country, over which the latter may be extended.
The
effect of the first difference is, on the one hand, to refine and
enlarge the
public views, by passing them through the medium of a chosen body of
citizens,
whose wisdom may best discern the true interest of their country, and
whose
patriotism and love of justice will be least likely to sacrifice it to
temporary or partial considerations. Under such a regulation, it may
well
happen that the public voice, pronounced by the representatives of the
people,
will be more consonant to the public good than if pronounced by the
people
themselves, convened for the purpose.[4]
In the light of this
contradistinction of the people and the public, the usage of the two
terms
"democracy" and "republic" has further evolved in modern
times. Democracy does not so much mean a form
of government, but a quality possessed
by certain governments, while a republic is more a form of government.
Democracy refers to: 1) the degree to
which the people effectively participate in the choice of those who
rule them,
and also 2) the degree to which they have
real possibilities of acceding to positions of authority themselves.
This
is the connotation we intend here. Thus, a monarchy may be a democracy
if it is
constitutional, with the monarch only a symbol and head of state, with
the
business of government handled by a parliamentary system based on
popular
suffrage, and with competing political parties. A republic, on the
other hand,
may restrict the "public" so that the business of government is
confined to a few. The more "the people" as a social mass is
recognized as "the public," i.e., a legally mature entity to
participate in the business of government, the more a political culture
can
develop its aptitudes toward democracy. We stress political culture
rather than
political institution because, while some degree of maturity may result
from
additional responsibility, the latter does not automatically bring
about the
former, and therefore the simple fact of erecting institutions
providing for
democratic government does not necessarily produce a democratic
political
complex.[5]
This leads us to what
we may
call the democratic fallacy of
representational mechanics, suggesting that just because people
vote, they
do not necessarily choose their representatives or participate in the
political
decision-making process; and the representative, because he has been
elected by
popular vote, does not necessarily represent "the people," nor does
he necessarily participate in political decision-making. The
ballot and the act of voting are symbols and rituals of democracy.
The point is easily demonstrated by the electoral process in most
communist-inspired regimes, where the voters are presented with a
single list
of candidates elaborated by the ruling party, where there is usually
over
ninety per cent participation in the voting process and over ninety per
cent
adherence to the party's single list, and where the representatives in
popular
assemblies usually endorse the political decision of the party
oligarchy. In
most Western "democracies" (as distinct from Eastern European
political regimes) the rituals of selection of candidates, elections
and
responsive representation are more "democratically" employed for
legitimization. However, that does not altogether alleviate the
democratic
fallacy of representational mechanics, the causes of which are the
phenomena of
the socio-political flux.
The realities of
interests and
their consciousness shape a political culture. "The people," in their
majority, are not in the habit of considering political participation
part of
their daily, weekly, or even monthly established schedules.[6] The grass-roots caucuses of political
parties hardly ever gather a significant percentage of the actual
voters. It is
consequently "interests" rather than "the people" that
concern themselves with the choice of candidates, and are eventually
voted on
at the voting booth. It is true that, as we saw, in terms of bourgeois
culture,
interests should be confounded with the people. A representative is
then the
point of convergence--or compromise --of interests, whether those of a
political party that endorses him or of his constituency. That factor
also
decides his actions and judgments on policy matters as a
representative. Where
he is elected on a strictly disciplined party ticket (see our later
discussion
of political parties), he may have to vote obediently according to the
party
stand. In such a case the representative is directly responsible to
his party,
through which he "represents" his constituency. But even in political
cultures with loose-knit political parties, where the candidate has to
rally
enough votes by appealing to enough interests to get elected, he does
not, once
elected, necessarily represent his constituency nor all the interests
that made
his election possible.
To begin with, even if
a
candidate aspires to represent all his constituents and not only those
who
voted for him--in other words, he strives for an ideal unanimity or
consensus
on the issues--the fact remains that there must have been some
discrepancy
between the platform and interests upon which he received his mandate,
and the
views and interests of those who did not vote for him. Assuming,
further, that
the interests which converged on his election are in different degrees
heterogeneous, which is the case in a pluralistic political culture,
the
representative will not even be able to conciliate in his actions and
judgments
all the time all those interests that voted for him. He may, for
example, have
rallied the votes of industrialists, both Catholic and Protestant, or
makers of
armaments as well as manufacturers of peace-time goods. Obliged to vote
on such
issues as abortion or the fate of an international conflict, he may
opt for a
direction incompatible with the interests of some of those who voted
for him
(although, in the process, he may find some adherence on particular
issues
among those constituents who did not vote for him). The factors
contributing to
these discrepancies include:
1. The
spatial/temporal
dimension of representation: A polity resorts to representational
mechanics to
permit the spatially scattered multitude to participate indirectly in
the
political process. If the representative assembly were viewed as a
gathering
of mandated agents restricted to a particular issue within the frame
of strict
instructions from their constituents, at every new stage of their
debates they
would have to go back and ask for new instructions. The more strictly
such a
process were applied, the more pointless would it make the
representational
mechanism. The broader the mandate of the representative to deal with
issues in
general and the longer his mandate, the freer he will be to deliberate
"in behalf" of his constituents. However, the broader and the longer
the mandate, the more fluid the "in behalf" part of the proposition
will become, giving more plasticity to our next point.
2. The personal
interests of
the representative: The representative is not a robot. Like his
constituents,
he has human needs and drives. His needs for food, sex and shelter may
be
partly displaced by his ambitions (domination drive) or sense of
security (to
maintain his power and position), but they are his human realities.
They will
influence his discharge of his duties. He will weigh his decisions in
the light
of his own interests as well as his standing and opportunities with the
interests controlling his constituency and their potentials to support
him. If
his mandate is broad and long, he may shift his policies to those which
suit
his personal interests. On the other hand, he may also be motivated by
the
following consideration.
3. The "higher"
national interests and values as he identifies them: These may, as
noted in our
discussion of bicameralism, motivate the representative with a broader
and
longer mandate to evaluate situations on the basis of valuational
considerations, detached from the immediate interests of his
constituents.
If we generalize these
factors
we will get an assembly of "representatives" not identical with the
sum of its constituent parts. While these factors further confirm the
democratic fallacy of representational mechanics, our emphasis of
democratic
fallacy should not discredit representational mechanics altogether.
Like other
political phenomena, representation aims at making possible what is
otherwise
impossible (the gathering of the multitude for political
participation). In the
process, like other socio-political phenomena, it does not exactly make
possible what was impossible, but produces some verisimilitude to that
effect.
Its shape depends on the potentials of the political culture, including
the
political maturity of "the people." This quality may not be easily
discernible. Will "the people'.' try to choose representatives in their
own image, expecting them to have radii of understanding and
identification
coincident with theirs? The assumption is reasonable at a given level
of
popular expectation, emancipation, bourgeois class consciousness, and
mistrust
of those whose wider range of identity and understanding goes beyond
the
"popular" grasp. In the words of Ortega y Gasset, "the
commonplace mind, knowing itself to be
commonplace, has the assurance to proclaim the rights of the
commonplace and to
impose them wherever it will."[7] Or
are the people inclined to delegate their
deliberative rights to whoever seems to have a better mind? The latter
alternative may lead to contradictory conclusions: either the people
have
enough maturity and self-confidence to trust their own judgment about
leaving
their affairs to superior minds, or they consider themselves inept to
deal with
the business of government and abdicate their prerogatives to whoever
claims
the power to govern. The latter proposition may lead to autocracy (the
opposite
of democracy) because the extreme of popular abdication would be
self-appointment by those who govern.
Where "the people"
are inclined to choose those like themselves, collateral
identification,
interest and understanding between the represented and the
representative are
implied. In the elitist case, while the representative is to represent
the
interests of the represented, his radii of understanding,
identification and
interests are expected to be broader than the people, and his ways of
securing
their interests may escape their grasp. These are, of course,
abstractions made
to analyze different attitudes. In actual life people are motivated by
a
complex of factors in which both identity with the representative and
his
competence and superiority are combined.
In effect, whether the
criterion is mediocrity (not necessarily in the pejorative sense, but
in the
sense that the elector is choosing the ordinary) or elitism (choosing
the
superior man), a lag is bound to develop between the angles of vision
of the
represented and the representative. For, as we saw, the mediocre
representative
will have to accommodate and compromise the views of. his different
constituents within his own, and his elevation in the social hierarchy
entails
the broadening of his radii of understanding, identification and
interests.
This phenomenon handicaps the modicum of democracy, because whether the
representative speaks in the name of and in behalf of the people and
administers their affairs and government in the spirit of mediocrity or
elitism
(but particularly the latter), with his expected broader radius of
vision he
can claim that his actions stem from his vision of the ultimate good,
the
ideological goal, or long-term policies beyond the people's radius of
understanding. He demands that they trust him farther than they can
see, and
thus the possibilities for abuse (corruption of power) are sown.[8]
Those elevated to
higher social
strata through involvement in the business of government may also
develop,
despite possible antagonisms arising from checks and balances of the
different
branches of government, a sense of identity based on their sharing of
the same
"business" interests. This likelihood confronts us beyond the danger
of having people of like interests and class controlling the different
branches
of government, with the possibility that they will develop common
characteristics and patterns of behavior. This phenomenon may lead to
political
professionalism and the growth of a bureaucratic and 'technocratic
oligarchy
perpetuating and upholding the "establishment" for its own--and their
own--sake. The likelihood would, of course, seem greater where popular
participation is limited. But it is such a pervasive reality of the
socio-political
flux that it grows even where sovereignty is supposed to lie with "the
people." To grasp this social growth, let us review the salient
criteria
for popular participation and continue our inquiry.
II.
Criteria For Popular Participation
If democracy evolves
into
elitism (aristocracy) and oligarchy, there must be social patterns and
procedures by which the sovereign rights are "democratically" passed
to the oligarchy which runs the machinery of the government. Indeed,
certain conditions, when met in a certain spirit,
can contribute to broader
popular participation in the political process; but when not respected,
these
same conditions can serve increasingly as tools for elitist or
oligarchic
arrangements. The extreme, if the conditions and spirit do not exist or
are not
recognized, would be autocracy. On the basis of past chapters, we can
broadly
identify three areas--the social, the constitutional and the
individual--where
certain conditions determine the nature and degree of the popular
participatory
processes of government:
1. Social
standards and framework.
a.
First among these conditions are the level
of economic development and distribution of wealth. In blunt terms,
for the
members of society to be interested in the political process
"democratically," their stomachs must be satisfied.[9] If they are hungry they may be politically
apathetic and thus vulnerable to exploitation; or they may become
hungry enough
to revolt. Of course, our "stomach" metaphor stands for all aspects
of economy and social justice. The economic factors do not influence
the
participatory process only at starvation level. When inflation hits the
economy
and real personal income goes down the electorate behaves negatively
towards
the party in power at the polls.[10]
Voters do not live by ideology alone--if
much at all--and considering the broad impacts of economy on politics
we may
add, nor do the candidates. For example, in polities like the United
States,
where finances figure prominently in campaigns and elections, the
uneven
distribution of wealth can bring the "democratic" process under the
control of those who control the economy. The disclosure laws of 1971
and
subsequent Watergate-connected investigations of campaign funds
revealed the
large role of corporate and big-business interests in financing and
influencing
the elections and the candidates. The 1974 electoral reform laws,
limiting
contributions by private interests, are aimed at reducing some economic
encroachments on the political process.
b. The general
level of education is also a
determining factor. Briefly, as Jefferson pointed out long ago,
ignorance and
democracy are incompatible. But
education, as we noted in our discussion of value-forming agencies,
can, under
certain circumstances of extensive control, railroad the members of
society--not a very democratic process.
c. The extension
of mass media and means of
communication is a crucial condition. To participate intelligently
in
social and political affairs, the members of society must be informed
and
mobile (in both mind and body) to grasp the issues and problems. But,
of
course, sophisticated control of the media can distort information and
handicap
the democratic process.
d.
Finally, there must be compatibility of
value patterns and a social consensus as to the virtues of the
democratic
and pluralistic process of government. For, while the other social
conditions
may reasonably exist, if the prevailing political culture has monist
tendencies
or if a social faction seeks and attains dictatorial power, democracy
will not
be practicable. In 1933, the Germans voted themselves out of the
parliamentary
system. Now, if there is consensus for a democratic government, it will
require
certain constitutional prerequisites:
2. Constitutional
framework.
a. Elections
are the first prerequisite for
a pluralistic government. Their outcomes, however, may run from a
rubber stamp
to a reasonable and just representation of "the people," depending on
whether they are haphazard, arranged to fit appropriate occasions, or regular and periodic; whether they are
without privacy, engendering
intimidation, or are secret; and
whether they present a choice between Tweedledum and Tweedledee or real alternatives. However, too short a
span between elections can disrupt continuity; secrecy may favor
duplicity; and
too many choices may cause factional dispersion.
b. Separation
of powers, in some effective
form, is necessary to provide checks and balances during the period the
powers
are given their mandates, i.e., between elections. However, as we
pointed out,
powers may check and balance each other even if they are not subject to
elections. Inversely, despite elections and separation of powers, there
may be
possibilities of collusion among like interests in charge of different
sectors.
But also, under different circumstances, acute antagonism and jealousy
among
the separated powers may cause disruption and paralysis of government.
c. Majority
rule is another characteristic
of pluralism. Properly applied, it can cure some ills that may arise
from the separation
of powers (such as excessive dispersion and conflict between branches)
by, for
example, giving the legislative majority the possibility of appointing
the
executive, as is the case in a cabinet form of government. But, of
course,
there may be problems in defining the majority in the social sense as
well as
within the governmental apparatus, and there is again the danger of
collusion
among branches.
d. Minority
rights are directly related to
majority rule. The assumption is that, politically speaking, the
minority is
the minority only because its approach to given problems at a given
time did
not receive a plurality of votes, yet it is still entitled, like the
majority,
to press its views democratically on the sovereign "people" and become,
perhaps with a different composition, on a different issue and at a
different
time, the majority. Of course, certain inherent characteristics in the
minority, such as ethnic, racial, religious or linguistic distinctions,
may
handicap it and make it likely to remain a minority, in which case it
will need
particular guarantees, such as a quota of participation in the
government, to
safeguard its identity and interests.
e. Recognition
of opposition is an
imperative constitutional prerequisite, for minority rights imply not
the
benevolence of the majority, but the prerogatives of those in the
minority to
defend their own rights and to criticize what they consider the
majority's
wrongdoings. The latter provides the occasion for the minority to show
the
public their arguments as to why they deserve to replace the incumbent
majority. Recognition of the opposition can also remedy the
possibilities of
collusion among the different branches and sectors of government.[11]
The recognition of
opposition
leads to individual liberties because, in the last analysis, opposition
to
authority is composed of members who should enjoy basic liberties in
order to
play an effective critical role:
3. Individual
liberty.
a. This
area demands certain key freedoms, the first of which is freedom
of the "person"--the simple right to be, to be
alive. It is, at an elementary level, what the individual is thankful
for in an
organized society; not to be mugged, robbed or killed. It is basically
the
reason Hobbes gave for the institution of the Leviathan. But the civil
authority instituted to protect life can itself become a threat to the
individual, and a point may be reached where the members of society may
be
thankful they are not subjected to arbitrary arrests, imprisonment,
torture and
summary executions. The writ of habeas
corpus implies first and foremost that the jailer has the body, alive! Freedom of the person in relation
to political authority involves such questions as innocence until guilt
is
proven, the circumstances under which one tray be required to bear arms
and go
to the front to shoot and be shot at, and the limits that can be
imposed on
one's movement (such as the question of whether a passport is a right
or a
privilege).
b. Freedom
to give free range to thought
may seem an obvious prerequisite and an inalienable freedom. Not so if
you
consider the extreme case of brainwashing. While brainwashing in the
literal
sense of psychological conditioning of a subject under strict control
has had
limited incidence, it dramatizes the possibility of conditioning the
thinking
process through propaganda, distorted or incomplete information, and
news
intoxication. It is directly related to the freedom to formulate an
opinion.
c. The freedom
to formulate an opinion differs
from the above, though, because it implies the additional dimension of
choice.
When one thinks, one does not necessarily formulate opinions. Thinking
can be
merely computational. The mathematician or the physicist thinks in
order to add
and subtract and the results are, so to speak, built in--not a matter
of
opinion. Indeed, totalitarian regimes have often hoped that their
scientists
would think but have no opinions. Of course, thinking and forming
opinions can
hardly be dissociated, and usually the control of one influences the
other. But
let us say that in a pluralist society the sergeant should not care
what you
think as long as you say, "Yes, sir," to his opinion and act
accordingly (although these days he does care, and armies manipulate
the
thoughts of their recruits too).
d. Freedom
of expression (both oral and
written) is the next requirement so that the opinion can be aired. The
freedom
of expression in itself, even without further impact, is, at least
psychologically, better than the silence of opinion. We are breaking
down these
closely interrelated individual liberties to show how at each stage
they can
constitute real or fictive freedoms. Being able to express one's
opinion may
indeed lessen the psychological weight of silence, but it will be of no
social
or political avail if it cannot be communicated. We
must thus introduce the further freedom of communication,
intertwined with the freedom of expression but not altogether
synonymous with
it.
e. Freedom
of communication means that the
spoken word can be heard and the written word can be read. For that,
channels
of communication are needed, and they may be more or less controlled.
Controls
need not be direct censorship but may be interwoven with the prevailing
social
patterns. Beyond the material facilities to be supplied, communication
can be
curbed through tacit control of publishers, broadcasting organizations
and
value-forming agencies, without giving the impression that the freedom
of
expression has been tampered with. Not every opinion is broadcast nor
is every
written word published. If such curbs are not imposed blatantly on the
basis of
obvious value-judgments and open censorship, a greater verisimilitude
of both
freedom of expression and of communication will exist. The unpublished
author
may blame himself for falling short of the standards and may doubt his
talents,
while in reality he is handicapped because he deviates from the
prevailing
norms.
f. Freedom
of association should be a
normal follow-up of the expression and communication of opinion because
the purpose
of airing a view is to find like minds who can unite for action. This
freedom,
however, does not necessarily follow the others and may be subject to
formal
limitations, even where the other liberties are respected, particularly
when it
results in an assembly. (There have been such instances as the ban on
the
Communist Party in the German Federal Republic between 1956 and 1968,
although
Communist literature was not suppressed.)
g. Freedom
of assembly is the stage of
deliberation and action; the point where the liberties of the
individual merge
with those of the group--a major conversion point which joins our
earlier
discussions. It puts in perspective the other individual freedoms,
beginning
with the crucial ones of giving free range to thought and formulation
of
opinions. It was man's claim to thought, qualifying him as a political
animal,
which impelled our inquiry in Chapter Two. That attribute set us on the
road
winding through values and symbols within the total environment and
culture. It
permitted us to realize that human thought, in socio-political terms,
was not
available in its pure state, but was reified by social semantics within
valuational and symbolic patterns, enhanced by value-forming agencies
in the
context of group dynamics. These social factors condition and restrict
individual thought. Freedom of assembly reflects these factors and even
in the
broadest sense implies limitations.[12] It
is limitative not only because of the
assembly's potentials to shape individual thought and values but also
because
of the sheer need of numerical combination for any individual thought
to have a
practical outcome.
From
the Individual to the Group: Political Parties
The conversion from
individual
to group action has two essential characteristics. First, those who
associate
with each other, even if they have similar opinions, will have to make
some opinion adjustments to fit the
principles for which their association or, in political terms, their
party
stands. However, as noted in Chapter Seven, these principles may be
more or
less fluid. Some parties such as Communist and some Socialist parties,
may
proclaim strict ideologies, while others may have a broad spectrum of
principles accommodating different shades of opinions, as do the
Democratic and
Republican parties in the United States.[13] In
this latter case, the party draws support
rather from the second characteristic of an association, its instrumentality for action, and in the
case of a political party, for political action: accession to political
control.[14] Of course, the party has to present an
outline, no matter how broad, of certain principles and policies,
because when
an association is constituted for action, that action should be given
some
semblance of direction. Thus, broadly speaking, a party is a group
created by
the people's association for political action, and as such will show
the
symptoms of the group. There will be need for representation,
leadership,
formulation of principles and policies, strategies and tactics-all this
influencing the party members whose individual freedom to give free
range to
their thoughts and to formulate opinions will be conditioned by their
association. In the process the top of the party hierarchy assumes
leverage for
political action with a broader radius of vision and understanding than
the
base, thus preparing to exercise governmental authority if elected.
The degree of
discrepancy in
the views of different strata of the party and the possibilities for
the higher
levels to impose their views on the lower, and eventually on the
voters, will
depend on the nature of the party and its social and constitutional
environment. The political party's goal, we must remember, is to gain
political
control within the range of possibilities offered by the constitutional
framework
and social standards, thus providing for the "democratic" passage of
the sovereign rights from "the people" to the ruling oligarchy: the
party should be voted into office.
We can, of course,
conceive of
an extreme where one ruling party imposes strict discipline on its
members and
controls the elections, as has been generally true of the regimes
controlled by
Communist parties. The oligarchy in such instances is the ruling body
of the
party with which the bureaucratic apparatus is fused and confused. We
thus
return to the monist conception of government, where the ruling
oligarchy, in
the name of an ideology whose principles it formulates and interprets,
exercises (or at least attempts) totalitarian control over all aspects
of life
in the country by populating the governmental bureaucracy and using it
to
control the social framework (including, besides the party apparatus,
other
value-forming agencies such as education and mass media) and the
constitutional
framework (including the elections and the "elected" bodies).
In different total
environments, however, political cultures lend themselves to less rigid
patterns of social and political fermentations and dynamics. In the
pluralist
contexts, the higher strata of political parties cannot afford, at
least
openly, to dictate from above drastic changes in the principles and
nature of
the party. A party in a pluralistic context is not a government. It
aims at
control of the government, for which it needs the vote of the electors.
It
should try to reflect the basic characteristics which identify it and
on the
basis of which it attracts popular votes. For example, when a party is
identified with stricter and well-defined principles, too much wheeling
and
dealing by the party bosses, compromising their principles to broaden
the
influence of the party, can either weaken the party or change its
nature and
structure, either make it lose voters or, if it gains voters and wins
the
election, weaken its position in government and handicap it in carrying
out
programs commensurate with its principles. Similarly, if a party
organized on a
broad spectrum of principles, mainly to serve as an instrument for
political
action, to attract the plurality of the voters, and to gain control of
the
government, started shrinking the spectrum of its principles when such
action
was not called for--i.e., when a polarization would not attract the
majority of
voters--is likely to lose voters.[15] Thus,
the party pattern, with its own
oligarchic variations and tendencies depending on particular political
cultures--provides the democratic hyphen between the sovereign people
and the
governmental machinery.
From
the Party to the Government
Our discussion of the
two
interrelated characteristics of political parties, namely, the
strictness or
broadness of their principles and their degree of service orientation
as
platforms for political contest, leads us again to political
philosophies about
the government's role in organizing social life. The program of a
political
party reflects what the party and those who vote for it believe the
government
should do. However, what a party will do once in power depends not only
on its
ideas about government but on the exclusivity of its program. When a party has strict principles, based on
particular beliefs, ideologies, myths or traditions radically distinct
from
those of other parties, even if its principles aim at the ultimate
abolition of
the government, it will have to use the machinery of government to
bring its
principles to bear on different aspects of life within the polity.
Thus,
paradoxically but understandably, parties advocating total governmental
control
of society, such as Fascists, and those aspiring to the final withering
away of
the state, such as Communists, both use governmental machinery to
control the
society and build the kind of society their principles call for.
On the other hand,
parties
accommodating a wide spectrum of principles tend to encourage diffusion of power within different
social sectors and the use of government as a regulatory body. Aiming
mainly to
gain control of the government, they try to rally many interests which,
in the
eventuality of success, will want the government to promote their
concerns but
not infringe their freedom of action. The result is usually a loose
party
reflecting a compromise among interests that are more likely to combine
with
each other as distinct from other combinations. Incidentally, the
process may
evolve towards a two-party system because where a party serves mainly
as a
rallying point to gain governmental control, those satisfied with a
particular
government join to support it--because of their interest rather than
their
principles--while the dissatisfied will join to defeat it. Of the
British
political party pattern, for example, Moodie says: "Historically it was
in
the interests of the crown and its chief advisers to try to unify their
supporters, an attempt that encouraged a similar unification among
their
parliamentary opponents if they were to be successful."[16]
This pattern has a
pragmatic rationale,
if one may say so, in that what secures the reasonableness of a polity
is
opposition and criticism, which can be achieved simply by providing two
sides.
While this rationale may apply at the level of conflicting interests,
it may
not altogether resolve the problem of variegated principles. Remember
our
discussion of the conversion of interests into values in Chapter Four
and the
latency of values to change. Even where the two-party pattern prevails,
as in
the United States and Britain, smaller parties with stricter principles
survive. In themselves, they may have little potential to expand in
traditionally pluralistic and pragmatic political cultures, but they
remain
indicators of extremes of principles-and interests--which could break
away if
the two major loose-knit parties, seeking to broaden their electoral
base,
overlapped to the point of becoming unrecognizable.
The diffusion of power
promoted
by the leagues of interest groups within a loose-knit party tends, when
the
party gains control, to turn the government into a regulatory agency
responding
to the pressures of the various interest groups--favoring more those
that
supported its party, but not neglecting those that did not support it
but may
in the future. Diffusion of power thus not only tends to confine the
areas of
governmental activities, but also shifts some weight from the
party--which we
called the hyphen between "the people" and the government--to the
interest groups. Such a pattern is the outcome of total environmental
factors,
taking different forms in different political cultures. The situation
we have
just depicted implies a certain stage of social evolution in modern
terms.
Where the pattern of
political
parties has evolved to be dominated by parties with a wide spectrum of
principles,
the implication is that the political culture approaches
consensus/conflict/dissent pattern we developed in Chapter Eleven
rather than
sharp antagonisms. That is, through the long political conflicts,
compromises
and cooperations, the political parties have come to a broad
understanding, not
only on the rules of the game, but also on the basic moral and ethical
norms at
the root of their different social and political principles, and the
modalities
for their compromise. Thus, for example, today the two major American
parties,
although different in their priorities and ways of going about solving
social
and political problems, basically claim to uphold the principles of
free and
competitive enterprise, and yet recognize the necessity for
governmental responsibility
where social justice is implicated. The Republicans lean more heavily
on the
first principle, the Democrats on the second[17]
--that is, if we generalize about the two parties and look only at
their modal
constituents. Otherwise, because of their broad spectrums, each houses
under
the same roof both people who believe in the least governmental
interference in
social and economic affairs, leaving them to the free play of liberal
economy,
and those who believe in governmental limitations on competitive,
private
interest-oriented activities, for the sake of public good, or rather in
consideration of those social strata which could suffer because of
excessive
freedom of private interests.
In different political
cultures, notably with different social philosophies about the role of
the
government, different political party patterns develop. In Britain, for
example, we saw how the parliamentary process grew out of the duality
-- and
duel -- of those who defended the royal prerogatives and the
bourgeoisie who
wanted their finger in the affairs of government, mainly to become
master of
their own affairs. This evolution crystallized the conservative faction
--
later the Conservative Party -- which wanted to conserve what had
traditionally
existed, and the liberal faction -- later the Liberal Party -- which
valued a
liberal economy and free enterprise. As each broadened its popular base
(a
process which, together with industrial development, prompted the
emancipation
of the larger population and focused on their problems in electoral
platforms),
social movements emerged, eventually developing into a third party --
the Labor
Party -- upholding the principle of social justice and socialist
management of
the country. After a period of transition in the early twentieth
century, the
Labor Party displaced the Liberal Party to become, together with the
Conservatives, one of the two major British political parties.
The British two-party
pattern
reflects earlier points about political and public attitudes favoring
this
pattern, among them the character of the British parliamentary process.
Inspired by the pragmatic approach to the need for criticism and
opposition,
the arrangement provides for essentially two components in the House of
Commons
-- one, the majority in power, and the other, an opposition recognized
as an
integral part of the legislature, watching for the shortcomings,
fallacies and
loopholes in the policies and actions of the party in power and serving
as the
parliamentary opposition loyal to the kingdom and the people. The
two-party
pattern is further enhanced by the British electoral arrangements,
namely the
"Cube Law" whereby the proportion of seats the winning party receives
in Parliament is the cube of the proportion of votes cast for it, a
rule that clearly
favors the winning party and handicaps the others, with the
discrimination
growing as the number of votes for the contesting parties diminishes.[18]
In Western Europe, as
we have
briefly reviewed, political, economic and social evolutions took
sharper turns
and, together with class consciousness of antagonistic groups, produced
multiparty patterns largely composed of parties with strict principles
(myths,
ideologies, traditions). Patterns are different, of course, in
different
political settings, but generally they cover a variety of principles
ranging
from the restoration of the traditional regimes, organization of the
society on
the basis of religious precepts, economic liberalism or limited
socialism, to
communism. Their principles are what each party believes a government
should be
and do. We saw, however, that within the European conjunctures,
different
beliefs, myths and ideologies clashed and compromised, because
abstractions of
declared principles submit to human and social realities. Party
hierarchies
modify their ends to avail themselves of means. The coexistence and
confrontation of parties with strict principles may lead to
coalitions--mostly
between fairly compatible parties which agree that their adversaries'
accession
to power would harm them and cause social upheavals beyond what they
could
tolerate. Sometimes, in moments of crisis, coalitions between less
compatible
parties also take place.
Thus, the evolution of
Western
European party coalitions has generally tended toward practices similar
to
those of the loosely knit parties with broad spectrums of principles.
In some
countries like post-World War II West Germany, a two-major-party
pattern has
emerged,[19]
and in France since the advent of the Fifth Republic, a coalition of
right of
center parties with a wide spectrum of principles has controlled the
government
and had some influence on the rapprochement of otherwise feuding
Communist and
Socialist parties on the opposition side. By and by, even the Communist
parties
of some countries such as Italy and France are accepting the bourgeois
rules of
the game and recognizing that in case of accession to power--probably
in
coalition with other parties, but even if alone--they may not be able
to
implement their totalitarian programs without disrupting the intricate
complex
of economic and social interests to the point of cutting their own
throats. In
effect, these Communist parties have slowly merged into the prevailing
bourgeois symbiosis.
A political party in
power,
then, does not do what it theoretically wants
to do, but what it can do--unless, of
course, it has played the parliamentarian game to gain power and
abolish the
system, as did the National Socialist Party in Germany in 1933. But
this latter
possibility can occur only under certain total environmental
conditions. In the
context of Western European political cultures with developed party
affiliations and intricate power complexes, even when one party can
muster a
majority and take control of the government, it has to adapt its
policies more
or less away from its abstract principles to fit into the social
realities, the
existing governmental bureaucracy, the constitutional checks and
balances and
the pressure of other political parties. Their common ground is the
business of
government and whether they compete, compromise or collaborate, they
have to
learn, master and absorb the ways of government: what we called in
Chapter
Three the specialization to control. In that context, those who aspire
to this
specialization develop common outlooks.
III.
The "Business" of Government: Politicians and
Bureaucrats
In its benign form,
the common
outlook of those in the business of government makes coalition
governments by
communist and liberal, conservative and socialist or monarchist and
republican
parties possible. It is reflected in the attitude of compromise that
may be
adopted by politicians despite their ideologies that split the people
at the
base, and thus rounds some of the edges of their conflicts to get on
with the
business of government. The less there are edges and the more the
collusion
coincides with class identification, the more the nature of government
may
move from democratic to oligarchic patterns. There may still be
popular
participation in the installation of authorities, but the people will
be
"informed" and "advised" as to whom they should choose to
hold authority and who will safeguard their best interests. The
assumption is
that, after all, whether mediocre or elite, those in the higher strata
of
social order, with their broader foresight and vision, are better
placed to see
who would serve best at representation and government. Informing and
advising
is not necessarily an outright imposition, but a process of
conditioning and
persuasion, notably through the value-forming agencies, as we
discussed
earlier. The elect will know better who the elite are. This was, in
essence,
the early premise of aristocracy[20]
-which eventually corrupted elitism with the assumption of hereditary
qualities
for government--and has also been the argument of regimes based on the
rule of
one ideological party.
While at a
revolutionary and
dynamic stage of social flux such a tendency may be qualified as
elitist, its
perpetuation can evolve into an oligarchy,
i.e., rule by a few--not necessarily the best qualified. To perpetuate
their
authority, those who govern will develop symbols and rituals of
identification
and qualification which, while giving them cohesion, will make their
group hard
to penetrate. The more it becomes closed with its own criteria of
affiliation,
the less will its intrinsic qualities of excellence be measurable by
social
standards, but will be asserted because of its political control.
The ruling class will
be elite
because .it is in power. That, as we saw in our discussion of power,
can be a
convincing argument in politics. While antagonisms may exist among the
components of an oligarchy, the conflicts and compromises will be like
those
between industrialists competing for a market. Their interests may
clash and,
where their survival is threatened by the competition, they may try to
eliminate each other. But if one cannot eliminate the other, or if such
elimination weakens the position of the survivor, allowing more
dangerous and
less compatible competitors to arise, they may agree to control the
market
(read "polity") through an oligopoly (read "oligarchy").
Even when one eliminates the other, the successor is likely to absorb
the
components of the defunct competitor because they are usable and
instrumental.
The common outlook of
those in
the business of government does not necessarily imply that they will
totally
identify with each other beyond certain bounds of their ideological,
religious
and economic differences. But where and to the extent they do, the
machinery of
government falls into oligarchic control, which will tend towards
exclusivity
as the "governing" common characteristics of its components become
more prominent, overshadowing their particular identities. Oligarchy
has both a
class and a professional component; a community of outlook among those
who are
in the business of government. Michels argued that it is a class in
itself,
perpetuating itself and recruiting itself.[21] It
is a class all right, but with the
particular trait that even where it does not consciously perpetuate
itself, it
grows out of the circumstances, because it is a social category on
which
organized society depends. In the generic sense, this political class
is a
phenomenon of the body politic. A society needs to be run, and those
assigned
to run it, or attracted to it, develop an angle of vision and interests
and
cultivate certain behavior and attitudes.[22] In
the structural sense, this political
class may require particular qualifications which may be tacitly or
expressly
instituted. The convergence of the generic and structural dimensions of
political and bureaucratic oligarchy with pluralism may be more or less
fluid
depending on the particular political culture.
Of course, extreme
fluidity, as
our earlier discussions have revealed, is not a reality. We may, for
example,
consider American political culture as fluid enough to permit those
with a bent
for it to join or let themselves be recruited into the political
current. We
soon find out, however, that certain backgrounds, milieux and means are
more
likely to introduce the individual into the political oligarchy. Of the
thirty-nine United States presidents, for example, twenty-two practiced
law;
and the overwhelming majority of senators and congressmen have legal
backgrounds. However, the social class background of the American
politicians
and bureaucrats has remained comparatively fluid. The relatively fluid
political recruitment process has permitted the political class to
coincide
more easily with the economically dominant class. Where the political
"class" is more structured, with symbols, rules and rituals of
recruitment, it can develop more distinctly from the economically
dominant
class, coinciding with it more or less. The Confucian state
examinations in
traditional China and their products, the Mandarin class, provide the
most
striking examples of a distinct and powerful political class--combined
with the
courtly aristocracy and military war lords.
We discussed in
Chapter Seven
the development of the business of government in the early middle ages
in
Europe, with ecclesiastic, clerical and aristocratic combinations. This
political oligarchy was recruited from different classes, with some
dealing in
public administration, others with the legal and organizational aspects
of
government. When the social and economic conditions in Europe evolved
to make
the bourgeoisie economically dominant, the business of government was
not
altogether wrested out of the hands of a political oligarchy which,
even when
overthrown as the agent of the old regime, had to be partly recomposed
and
reinstated by the new social and economic currents to deal with the
business of
government and to form and initiate the new political class. Many of
the
deputies of the French Third Estate during the revolution were liberal
aristocrats
and clergymen. Among them was the striking Charles Maurice de
Talleyrand,
Bishop of Autun, who floated with the changing tides and became
successively
popular representative to the National Assembly in 1789, Napoleon's
minister of
foreign relations in 1798, head of the provisional government in 1814
(which
forfeited the Napoleonic empire and called on Louis XVIII to restore
the old
regime), negotiator for peace on behalf of France at the Congress of
Vienna,
and French ambassador to London under Louis Philippe in the 1830's.
Michels
reported in 1908 that the French Republic had a good number of
aristocrats in
its diplomatic service and armed forces, and that no less than
sixty-one of the
584 deputies in the French legislature belonged to the old aristocracy.[23] Many of the present French fonctionnaires
claim aristocratic
descendence.[24] In reality, however, they are more products
of the bourgeois culture in terms of their social roles, but are
conscious of
their traditional governmental technocracy.
The governmental
oligarchy or
the political class within a society has a managerial quality which, to
some
extent, remains distinct from the economic, social and other currents,
interacts with them and, while being influenced by them, influences
them in its
turn. Where it has remained less structured, it is more easily
intertwined with
the other social currents--although that is the exception rather than
the rule;
and even in the United States where there has been less of a
governmental and
bureaucratic tradition, those in the business of government, whether
executives, judges or politicians, develop behavioral and attitudinal
traits
and "class" consciousness, thus comprising "the
establishment."
As it becomes more
structured,
the political oligarchy develops its own jargon, symbols and modes of
behavior
which are socially identifiable and, at the same time, both accepted
and
resented by those who submit to it. The French call the governmental
class
"ils" (they), and the
British call it "they."[25]
"They" are best off in their "establishment" milieu if they
have had the right background and have learned the tricks of the trade.
In
France, the business of government has had a long tradition with its
own tacit
and explicit processes of formation, selection and recruitment--to a
large
degree because of the governmental control and organization of the
educational
system. Certain educational backgrounds and training patterns are not
only
indispensable for becoming part of the administrative machinery of
government,
but are favorable assets for an active political life in general.[26] Although the British Civil Service has not
had a systematic structure comparable to the French and those of other
continental polities, mainly because of its particular evolution and
characteristics,
it has, because of Britain's past role as a world power and an imperial
administration, and the complexities of modern bureaucracy, gained
considerable
status and leverage in the country's political life.[27]
It may seem that
starting with
democracy as direct popular participation in politics which can evolve
into
"aristocracy" (elitism) and oligarchy, we are implying that this
oligarchy--or political class--is synonymous with the bureaucratic
apparatus of
the government. Synonymous it is not, because it is, as such, not the
holder of
sovereignty, which is supposed to be held by those the governmental
bureaucracy
is to serve. If we have given an impression that the machinery of
government is
omnipotent, it is because bureaucracy does indeed, in many ways, appear
to
escape the force of gravity of those who are invested with sovereign
rights and
instead has them gravitate around it.[28] The
Fourth French Republic was a succession
of unstable ministerial cabinets which came and went at the whim of the
National
Assembly, but political organization was maintained because of a stable
bureaucratic infrastructure. The phenomenon is not new. De Tocqueville
had
already remarked over a century ago that "since [1789] the
administrative
system has always stood firm amid the debacles of political systems."[29] The Fifth Republic has further enhanced the
role of technocrats and bureaucrats in policy-making while instituting
appropriate controls for detailed policy evaluation within the
executive branch
rather than the legislative.[30]
As for the British, as
Max
Nicholson puts it, "British administration has... very gradually
changed
from that of a picked band of permanent officials operating under the
aegis of
a succession of individual Ministers to that of a succession of
Ministers being
grafted more or less temporarily on to the permanent and firmly
structured
organism of a Department of State."[31] Nicholson
asks to what extent the "true
authority to exercise sovereignty, which long since passed from the
Crown to
Parliament, and thence to the Cabinet and thence largely to the Prime
Minister,
has in Practice passed once more from the Ministerial level as a whole
to the
permanent heads of the Civil Service?"[32] He
then depicts a portrait in which, indeed,
the minister is not always the party who has his way in the
administration of
his area of responsibilities.
The governmental
bureaucracy
and technocracy are not, of course, all there is to the political
oligarchy,
but one of the basic dimensions making oligarchy the most likely
pattern of
political participation, representation and control.[33] Even the autocratic form, at the opposite
end of the spectrum from democracy, will have to tend towards
oligarchy, be it
only for the indispensability of bureaucratic and technocratic
delegation of
power. Indeed, autocracy, in the
sense of self-appointment to government, can be only a passing moment;
and to
evolve from what amounts to a usurpation into a functioning machinery,
it will
have to rely on a bureaucracy, hence become dependent on it, and in one
way or
another share power with it.
The phenomenon has
recurred
throughout history, and while the institutional turgescence (see next
chapter)
of a bureaucratic oligarchy may at times cause a state to decline, the
leftovers of that bureaucracy, if they still bear some competence, can
secure
some continuity for the culture and personality of the defunct state.
Germany
after World War II presents, to some extent, a recent example. Even
though the
Nazi officials were partly eliminated, there were those, like Adenauer,
of the
pre-Nazi era who could assure the continuity of the German political
identity.
Another more remote, but perhaps more striking example is the Persian
governmental bureaucracy and technocracy which, through the ages, since
the Achemenid
Empire's collapse in the fourth century B.C., served successive waves
of less
sophisticated invaders and autocrats and adapted itself to each rule,
but at
the same time converted them to acceptable governments for the country
and
secured not only a modicum of continuity for the culture, but also its
propagation in the neighboring areas through the powers-that-be.[34] Similar roles of the bureaucratic apparatus
can be evoked in China and to some extent in Italy after the collapse
of the
Roman Empire. While in China the role of the Mandarins in the
continuity of the
political culture is more identifiable than it is in Persia, the
vicissitudes
it encountered were less momentous, disruptive and colorful than those
of the
Iranian plateau. As for Italy, the dispersion of the Roman culture in
Europe
and the development and intertwining with it of the Germanic and
Christian
patterns make identification of the predominant strain of classical
Roman
bureaucratic class (although existing) more complex.
As our illustration of
the
preponderance of bureaucracy, technocracy and political activism in a
polity
has evolved within the context of degrees of popular participation,
running
along the spectrum of democracy, aristocracy (elitism), oligarchy and
autocracy, it has reverted us to our discussion of the specialization
to
control, suggesting the tendency of polities towards oligarchy in
political
participation and government. However, we need to distinguish between
political
preponderance of a bureaucratic oligarchy and its possible social
pervasion.
One does not automatically imply the other. The development of
political
control into social control depends on the complex of factors we have
reviewed
so far. A bureaucratic oligarchy at the service of a monolithic
tax-taking
empire presenting a "confusion" of powers may wield great military
and administrative control but not interfere with broad areas of social
activities. Also limited may be the social role of a government
bureaucracy in
a polity with diffusion of power in a liberal economy, as was the case
of the
United States in decades past. The bureaucratic oligarchy may
increasingly gain
leverage in social activities where the prevailing political philosophy
calls
for greater concernment (as discussed in Chapter Twelve), resulting
from
complexity and heterogeneity of a technologically developing society
and/or
imposed by an extreme monolithic totalitarian control.
IV. The
Role of Government
In our discussion of
political
parties, we referred to their philosophies, reflecting some of the
modern
political thoughts covered earlier. Some, as we saw, would claim a goal
of
total abolition of the state, which, we noticed, could paradoxically
turn into
totalitarian policies similar to some at the other end of the spectrum
advocating
total state control over social life. Between these extremes is a range
of
possibilities for more or less diffusion of power, depending on the
political
cultures and combinations of party philosophies. The extremes and the
possibilities between them provide the range of what can be expected of
government.[35]
There is, at one
extreme, the
nonexistence of government, i.e., anarchy. Our discussions in Chapter
Twelve
revealed that anarchy in the ideal sense of ultimate human
consciousness, and
order and justice without government, is unlikely for social
organization. Not
only are other human needs and drives not always compatible with the
sociological needs for order and justice, but the very fact of social
relations
calls for organization; organization implies distribution of tasks;
distribution of tasks in any reasonably complicated social situation
will call
for specialization, in turn causing differentiations which, as we have
seen,
will set standards and hierarchies. Hierarchy produces classification
and hence
classes, which then institute an authority to safeguard the privileges
of
certain classes. This is, in effect, a Marxian simplification of the
process.
We have seen that the political dimension is more complex. In fact,
beyond the
ideal stage, the anarchist thinkers themselves have more or less
recognized the
need for the ground rules of social organization--which they have
wanted to be
apolitical.
To the question, "What
will these people who talk of abolishing government put in place of
it?"
Proudhon answers:
It is
industrial organization that we will put in place of government ....
In
place of laws, we will put contracts.-- No more laws voted by a
majority, nor
even unanimously; each citizen, each town, each industrial union, makes
its own
laws.
In
place of political powers, we will put economic forces.
In
place of the ancient classes of nobles, burghers, and peasants, or of
business
men and working men, we will put the general titles and special
departments of
industry: Agriculture, Manufacture, Commerce, &c.
In
place of public force, we will put collective force.
In
place of standing armies, see will put industrial associations.
In
place of police, we will put identity of interests.
In
place of political centralization, we will put economic centralization.[36]
In effect, Proudhon
proposes a
combination of cooperative communal and professional interest groups
within the
broad context of a network of multinational corporations. According to
anarchists the obstacle to this scheme, we noted, is political
government which
has to be abolished. This proposition, however, defeats the purpose of
an
anarchist party's participation in the political process. We saw that
this
apparent paradox is circumvented by Communist parties which aim at
gaining control
of the government and using it to abolish private property capitalism,
consequently causing its instrument, the state, to wither away. The
snag in
these approaches is that politics is taken as something dismountable
from
within the social context, and private property capitalism as its only
inspiration. Private property and manipulation of capital are only part
of the
components which feed power, which in turn is converted into authority.
The
aggressive man who runs for office does not necessarily have
capitalistic aims.
His aims, more often than not, are psychological. They are what
Françoise
Giroud identified as the dilatation of ME, for power, position and
recognition.[37] The society gives in a little and uses a lot
of his ambitions and psychological bent for its own organization.
As we have seen,
politics is an
integral, interwoven part of the social flux. Its essence is the need
for
authority (you may call it whatever you like) and, depending on the
political
culture and its total environment, it may be dispersed arid diffused
more or
less, but only to certain limits. Indeed, the diffusion of power in the
United
States ironically presents some of the characteristics of the society
Proudhon
had in mind. The federal, stage and local governments are impregnated
with the
economic power of industrial corporations run by ambitious executives
who do
not necessarily represent the views of any particular capitalist but of
capitalism per se and anonymous
shareholders. The workers' unions are also run by an oligarchy of
aggressive
executives. These interest groups influence the parties and, through
their
lobbies, the government. With a cynical twist, we may find that the
military-industrial complex has gone a long way toward replacing
standing
armies with industrial associations. Of course, this is not what
Proudhon had
in mind. He meant industrial competition instead of war. But in many
ways, the
multinational corporations are developing in that direction. As gunboat
diplomacy becomes increasingly obsolete for imposing economic
supremacy, the
multinational corporations find the fiction of sovereignty rather in
the way of
their expansion. Thus, with the development of the complex, modern,
industrial
society, a diffusion of power may seem to take place.
The statement, as
usual, needs
qualification. The central government does not wither away; it may even
grow
bigger and more proliferous because, as the society grows in material
complexity and interest groups become politically involved and mesh,
the
government is called upon to regulate a greater number of fields. As it
does,
depending on the magnitude of the interplaying power complexes within
the
society, it may extend its authority within the different fields of its
competence to the structure or substance of those fields.[38] It is the breadth of the fields and the
depth of governmental involvement in their structure or substance that
can
indicate the nature of governmental control within a spectrum going
from the
ideal state of anarchy to totalitarianism. The degree of control also
depends
on the prevailing political philosophies within a culture. We may
conceive a
chart indicating breadth and depth of governmental involvement (see
below).
Our chart shows how,
in modern
political terms, the state is likely to become pervasive without
initial
totalitarian intentions, and yet how the proliferation of its
intervention in
different social, economic, educational, cultural and other domains can
easily
tip over into excessive control.
The totalitarian
concept of the
state (I say "state" because the ultimate totalitarian goal is to
unify all aspects of life, of which the government is only the
political
instrument) was posited by Mussolini as follows:
A
single party, so that economic discipline may be accompanied by
political
discipline and so that rising above contrasting interests all may be
bound
together by a common faith.
Nor is
this enough. After the single party there must be the totalitarian
State, that
is to say the State which absorbs all the energies, all the interests,
all the
hopes of a people in order to transform and potentiate them.
And
this is not yet enough. The third and last and most important condition
is to
live a period of high ideal tension.[39]
Chart
At the Nuremburg Trials, Albert
Speer, German minister for armaments and war production and Hitler's
architect,
depicted Hitler's totalitarianism as follows:
...Hitler's
dictatorship differed in one fundamental point from all its
predecessors in
history. His was the first dictatorship in the present period of modern
technical development, a dictatorship which made complete use of all
technical
means for the domination of its own country.
Through
technical devices like the radio and the loudspeaker, eighty million
people
were deprived of independent thought. It was thereby possible to
subject them
to the will of one man ....
Earlier
dictators needed highly qualified assistants, even at the lowest level,
men who
could think and act independently. The totalitarian system in the
period of
modern technical development can dispense with them; the means of
communication
alone make it possible to mechanize the lower leadership. As a result
of this
there arises the new type of the uncritical recipient of orders
....Another
result was the far-reaching supervision of the citizens of the State
and the
maintenance of a high degree of secrecy for criminal acts.
The
nightmare of many a man that one day nations could be dominated by
technical
means was all but realized in Hitler's totalitarian system.[40]
However,
totalitarianism does
not necessarily imply the imposition of a monolithic state on a country
by a
party using sophisticated mass media and modern propaganda techniques.
A
theocratic state can attain high degrees of control without electronic
gadgets.
Once the mind is conquered, it can serve as the agent of the authority
without
many intermediaries. Christian, Islamic, and Buddhist societies have at
times
created totalitarian authorities through the power of religion.
Totalitarianism
is rather a concept which refers to the relationship-between the
individual and
the social authority. In that sense a community, or a commune in the
communist
sense, may constitute a total entity regulating all aspects of life
through a
homogeneous value pattern-thus constituting the point where the ideals
of
anarchy and totalitarianism converge.
*
* *
Our loop thus comes to
its
point of departure at the beginning of the last chapter. We began at
the
heights of sovereignty and, while keeping in the background the complex
canvas
of the socio-political flux we had painted in the preceding chapters,
traced
the contours of political institutions from the state and the different
aspects
of government down to the people, and then, in this chapter up again
through an
overview of "democratic" popular representation and political parties
back to the state. Out of our discussion of polity, a three-dimensional
pattern
has emerged, which we could visually summarize thus:
Fig.
14.1
On the basis of what
we have
covered, we may note that different levels of different dimensions in
Fig. 14.1
combine to reflect the realities of particular political cultures. As
we have
seen, some combinations are more likely than others, and some, at the
extremes,
are more theoretical than practical. None, however, presents any
ready-made
formula of government for all times and all places. Not only because
the total
environment of a polity is ever-evolving, but also because its
institutions and
authority patterns are themselves made of man, and man escapes simple
architectural and mathematical formulations.
[1]
"Let that which
touches all be approved by all."
[2]
David
Wechsler, The Measurement and Appraisal of Adult
Intelligence, 4th ed. (Baltimore: Williams and Wilkins, 1958), p.
148.
[3] The Federalist, No. 14.
[4] The Federalist, No. 10. See also Alfred De Grazia, Public and Republic: Political Representation in America (New York: Knopf, 1951).
[5] On democracy see, for example, Thomas Jefferson, On Democracy, ed. Saul K. Padover (New York: Penguin, 1946); A. D. Lindsay, The Modern Democratic State, Vol. I (London: Oxford Univ. Press, 1943); and Henry B. Mayo, An Introduction to Democratic Theory (New York: Oxford Univ. Press, 1960).
[6] Sidney Verba and Norman H. Nie, Participation in America (New York: Harper and Row, 1972).
[7] José Ortega y Gasset, The Revolt of the Masses (New York: Norton, 1960), p. 18.
[8] On the question of representation, see notably Carl J. Friedrich, The New image of the Common Man (Boston: Beacon, 1950); also his Man and His Government., notably Ch. 17; and his Constitutional Government and Democracy: Theory and Practice in Europe and America, 4th ed. (Waltham, Mass.: Blaisdell, 1968), notably Ch. 14; Hanna F. Pitkin, The Concept of Representation (Berkeley: Univ. of California Press, 1967); John P. Roche and Murray S. Stedman, Jr., The Dynamics of Democratic Government (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1954); and Robert J. Pranger, The Eclipse of Citizenship: Power and Participation in Contemporary Politics (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1968).
[9]
Giuseppe DiPalma,
Apathy and Participation (New York: Free
Press, 1970).
[10] Gerald H. Kramer, "Short-term Fluctuations in U. S. Voting Behavior," in APSR, 65:131-143 (1971).
[11] See Robert A. Dahl, ed., Political Oppositions in Western Democracies (New Haven: Yale Univ. Press, 1966), notably Chs. 11, 12 and 13; and also his Regimes and Oppositions (New Haven: Yale Univ. Press, 1973).
[12] For a discussion of this phenomenon in terms of group dynamics see, for example, Grant McConnell, Private Power and American Democracy (New York: Knopf, 1966); Theodore J. Lowi, The End of Liberalism: Ideology, Policy, and the Crisis of Public Authority (New York: Norton, 1969) and his The Politics of Disorder (New York: Basic Books, 1971).
[13] Kay Lawson, The Comparative Study of Political Parties (New York: St. Martin's, 1976).
[14] David Butler and Donald Stokes, Political Change in Britain: Forces Shaping Electoral Choice (London: Macmillan, 1969).
[15] For some basic studies of political parties see Austin Ranney and Willmoore Kendall, Democracy and the American Party System (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1956); Maurice Duverger, Political Parties (London: Methuen, 1954); also his Party Politics and Pressure groups; Seymour M. Lipset, "Party Systems and the Representation of Social Groups," European Journal of Sociology, 1:5085 (1960); Frank J. Sorauf, Political Parties in the American System (Boston: Little, Brown, 1964); Samuel J. Eldersveld, Political Parties: A Behavioral Analysis (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1964); and Joseph La Palombara and Myron Weiner, eds., Political Parties and Political Development (Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1966).
[16] Moodie, The Government of Great Britain, p. 64.
[17] See notably Key, Public Opinion, p. 67.
[18] For further details see M. G. Kendall and A. Stuart, "The Law of the Cubic Proportion in Election Results," British Journal of Sociology, 1:183196 (1950); also D. E. Butler, The Electoral System in Britain Since 1928 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963).
[19] The contrast between the fragility of the democratic and parliamentary process during the Weimar Republic in Germany after World War I and the rather effective patterns of government in West Germany after World War II can, of course, be attributed to a number of factors. Among them we might mention that the Weimar Republic had the Prussian components of the German political culture, with its authoritarian traditions favoring the National Socialists' para-military approaches to political activism, while the division of Germany into East and West after World War II left the Federal Republic with the western Lander, which since the French Revolution have had a longer exposure to modern democratic and parliamentary forms of government. The River Elbe in Germany has often been considered the appropriate demarcation line between Western and Eastern Europe.
[20] "Aristo-cracy" in Greek means rule by the élite.
[21] Michels, Political Parties, notably pp. 377 ff.
[22] For a discussion of this topic see Max Weber, The Theory of Social and Economic Organization (New York: Oxford Univ. Press, 1951); and B. L. Wynia, "Federal Bureaucrats' Attitudes Toward a Democratic Ideology," in Public Administration, 34:156-162 (1974).
[23] Michels, Political Parties, p. 379.
[24] Francois de Negroni, La France Noble (Paris: Sevil, 1974).
[25] See, for example, Laurence Wylie, Village in the Vaucluse, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1964), for the case of France; and Richard Hoggart, The Uses of Literacy (Fairlawn, N.J.: Essential Books, 1957), notably pp. 62 ff., for the case of Britain.
[26] The French system of the grandes écoles, among them l'Ecole Polytechnique, Eocle Normale Supérieure and Ecole Nationale d'A dministration in particular, not only produces the bulk of the French public administrators--often referred to as the "mandarins" in analogy with the traditional Confucian civil service which virtually ran China--but forms many others outside the strict governmental structures who influence the country's political currents.
[27] See notably Frank J. Goodnow, Politics and Administration: A Study in Government (New York: Macmillan, 1900); Charles S. Hyneman, Bureaucracy in a Democracy (New York: Harper, 1950); Philip Selznick, Leadership in Administration: A Sociological Interpretation (Evanston, Ill.: Row, Peterson, 1957); James G. March and Herbert A. Simon, Organizations (New York: Wiley, 1959); Brian Chapman, The Profession of Government: The Public Service in Europe (London: Allen & Unwin, 1959); and F. Ridley and Jean Blondel, Public Administration in France (New York: Barnes and Noble, 1964).
[28] For a discussion of bureaucracy and its relation to the elective body see Samuel Krislov, Representative Bureaucracy (New York: Prentice-Hall, 1974).
[29] Alexis de Tocqueville, The Old Regime and the French Revolution (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday Anchor, 1955), p. 202.
[30] See notably Victor Silvera, "Reflexion sur la stabilite gouvernementale et l'action administrative depuis 1958," La Revue Administrative, 17:554-555 (1964); and Michel Crozier, The Bureaucratic Phenomenon (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1964).
[31] Max Nicholson, The System: The Misgovernment of Modern Britain (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967), p. 187.
[32] Ibid.
[33] Guy Benveniste, The Politics of Expertise (Berkeley: Glendessary, 1972).
[34] Besides the well-known initiation of Alexander into a Persian kingly Weltanschauung, as related by Plutarch and others, the successive waves of Arabs, Turks and Mongol invaders used Persian administrators to control their newly conquered empire. See, for example, E. Denison Ross, The Persians (Oxford: Clarendon, 1931); A Mirror for Princes (New York: button, 1951); Nizam A1-Mulk, The Book of Government or Rules for Kings, 1086-1091, (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1960); Ala-ad-Din 'Ata-Malik Juvaini, The History of the World-Conqueror, 1252-1260?, 2 vols, (Manchester, England: Manchester Univ. Press, 1958); and Gaston Wiet, "L'Islam" in Histoire Universelle II, 37-139.
[35] See notably the articles on the subject in The American Scholar, 19: (1950), by Louis M. Hacker, "The Limits of Intervention," 481-486; Charles E. Lindblom,, "Empirical Problems and Particular Goals," 486-488; and Max Lerner, "State Capitalism and Business Capitalism," 488-491.
[36] Proudhon, The General Idea of the Revolution, Seventh Study.
[37] Francoise Giroud, La Comedie du Pouvoir (Paris: Fayard, 1977), p. 231.
[38] Most Western European governments have instituted economic and social control through planning organisms of some kind. Examples of such bodies are the French Commissariat General de Planification, the British National Economic Development Council, the Dutch Central Planning Bureau and the Italian National Economic Program Commission.
[39] Address to the National Corporative Council, Nov. 14, 1933, in Mussolini, Fascism, pp. 60-61.
[40] Proceedings of the International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg, XXII, pp. 406-407, quoted in Bullock, Hitler, p. 380. On totalitarianism see also Harry Eckstein and David E. Apter, "Totalitarianism and Autocracy: Introduction," in their Comparative Politics: A Reader (New York: Free Press, 1963), pp. 433-440; and Carl Friedrich and Zbigniew K. Brzezinski, Totalitarian Dictatorship and Autocracy, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1966) .