Chapter
7
Value/Norm-Forming
Agencies
and Processes
'Tis
Education forms the common mind,
Just
as
the Twig is Bent, the Tree's inclin'd.
Alexander
Pope
Since
every life experience and every encounter contribute to the formation
of values
and attitudes in the members of society, it is not always easy to
identify
values and attitudes as functions of a particular agency. Above all,
the social
fluid is pregnant with power and flows under the impulse of the
weightier parts
of the society which hold that power -- the power complex itself being
both cause
and consequence of the value system which the forming agencies promote.
The
social complex, in its fermentations and dynamics, embraces agencies
and
institutions and transcends them. Socialization, in its encompassing
connotation, is carried out by the society as a whole. While in this:
chapter
we will concentrate on family, peer group, church, educational system,
ideological parties and mass media as value-forming agencies, they do
not cover
the value-forming process completely. Their study is a logical step
towards
understanding political institutions and structures, which we will
cover in later chapters and which are more
closely related to those normative areas we identified in our last
chapter as
legal.[1]
I.
Family
To discover how
society disseminates its values and
inculcates its members with them, we can perhaps find a
point of
departure in our earlier discussion of values as the content of the
group. We
noticed that there was one group the human being could not do
without--namely,
the immanent group, out of which he emanates. Until the day when
test-tube
babies become the normal method of procreation, we need a man and a
woman to do
the job. Because of this context and the comparatively long period of
weaning
and rearing, the first germs of social behavior are inculcated within
the
family. Physiologically and traditionally, the male-female couple
constitutes
the nucleus.
The family is the
early natural
habitat of the child, and parents are the first likely potentates he
encounters. They ark also the most likely persons with
whom the child will establish his first relationships, which,
though obviously functional, are essentially affectional, providing
bases for
the formation of values. It is therefore understandable that
recognition of the
family's authority and responsibility towards the child has been a
prevalent
social trend throughout human history.[2]
Exceptions to this
general
pattern may occur during abrupt social changes and revolutions, when
the newly
installed power structures may need to alienate the new generations
from the
old for an overhaul of the value system. But then, at least so far in
the
history of mankind, the role of the family as a value-forming agency
has again
been recognized and restored. In recent times, National Socialists in
Germany,
early Soviets and Chinese Communists, among others, have attempted the
systematic alienation of the generations by indoctrinating the young
through
other value-forming agencies (education, the party organization and
mass media)
against the values of their families. The Nazi experience lasted only a
short
while, but its impact was rapid because, as we saw earlier, it promoted
values
based on myths rooted in German folklore and culture. Thus, in the
German
experience, the indoctrination of the younger generations soon pacified
the
older generations and the family could again play a role as
value-forming
agency -- although its influence was reduced by other agencies, as we
shall
discuss later. The Nazis were indoctrinating the younger generation not
so much
against the traditional values of the family as against the more recent
bourgeois and proletarian values and ideologies that had impregnated
large
social segments, rivalizing the Nazi myth.[3]
In the Soviet Union
the need to
counter the traditional values of older segments of the family also
arose,
beyond ideological considerations, for the practical needs of a system
which
had to mobilize the rising generations in a revolutionary economic and
social
outlook. What the Soviet regime had inherited from the Tzar was not a
pre-communist, saturated capitalism, as depicted by Marx, but a
backward,
agricultural and devastated economy. Before learning the ideological
intricacies of Marxism and Leninism, the young generation had to learn
discipline, punctuality and sound working habits. Lenin had said, "Put
a
Muzhik on a tractor and you will have Socialism." To introduce
a Muzhik to a tractor was
not an easy job, but the Soviets were set on accomplishing it. There
was also,
of course, the ideological premise of reducing the role of the
bourgeois
family, which was anathema to the edification of communism. But it was
only the
"bourgeois" dimension of the family-that part which made of the
family an instrument of production and consumption in the
feudal-capitalist
system -- that the Soviets wanted to get rid of. By the early 1930's,
when things
had settled down and the Stalin regime needed a more controllable
social base
on which to operate, the family regained its role as value-forming
agency
within the new Soviet social structure.[4] Here
is how A. S. Makarenko, the Soviet
pedagogue whose A Book for Parents
has been a best-seller in the Soviet Union
for three decades, sees the role of the Soviet family:
The
family becomes the natural primary cell of society, the place where the
delight
of human life is realized, where the triumphant forces of man are
refreshed,
where children -- the chief joy of life -- live and grow.
Our
parents are not without authority either, but this authority is only
the
reflection of social authority. In our country the duty of a father
toward his
children is a particular form of his duty toward society. It is as if
our
society says to parents:
You
have joined together in goodwill and love, rejoice in your children and
expect
to go on rejoicing in them. That is your own personal affair and
concerns your
own personal happiness. But in this happy process you have given birth
to new
people. A time will come when these people will cease to be only a joy
to you and
become independent members of society. It is not at all a matter of
indifference to society what kind of people they will be. In handing
over to
you a certain measure of social authority, the Soviet state demands
from you
correct upbringing of future citizens. Particularly it relies on a
certain
circumstance arising naturally out of your union -- on your parental
love ....
Parental
authority in Soviet society is authority based not only on the
delegated power
of society, but on the whole strength of public morality, which demands
from
parents that at least they should not be morally depraved.[5]
A Soviet decree of
July 8,
1944, dealt with many family matters in bourgeois terms, such as the
illegitimate child, unwed mother or multistage and complicated divorce
procedures. Some futurist communal concepts of the old guard have
lingered,
such as those of economist S. Stroumiline, who recognized that parents
are not
necessarily good educators and that the child, as of the moment when
his
umbilical cord is cut, becomes a subject with rights, whose education
should be
entrusted by the society to gifted and competent educators.[6] But the mainstream of contemporary Soviet
family life is oriented by the basic ideas and goals of the 1944
decree, with a
Victorian puritan morality
idealizing "psychological 'forces of cohesion'; feelings of love, kinship, duty, family solidarity and
responsibility."[7] There is, however, a growing tendency on the
part of Soviet families to transfer an ever greater part of the
responsibility for
child rearing to social institutions. Beyond the ideological
acquiescence that
is increasing among the new generation of parents born and raised after
the
October Revolution, this development is due also to social evolutions
similar
to those in the industrial West after the Victorian Era. Children can
become
time-consuming for ambitious and socially involved parents.[8] The 1977 Constitution of the USSR obliges
Soviet citizens to devote themselves to the upbringing of their
children
(Article 66).
The Chinese experiment
of breaking the traditional
value-forming role of the family presents its own particular features.
We saw
earlier how ancient and deep-rooted filial piety was in China. The
whole of
Chinese traditional culture and Confucian orthodoxy was interwoven with
the
kinship system.[9] Before the advent of the People's Republic
of China, the modernizing elements had already initiated the "family
revolution," notably during the New Culture Movement which started in
1917
and culminated in the May 4th movement of 1919. The general thrust of
the
"family revolution" was to transform the kinship ties and lineage
systems, which were virtually the patterns of social and political
structures,
into a more westernized nuclear family arrangement. The social trend in
this
direction progressed, not always evenly, during the Civil, Japanese and
Second
World Wars. Since 1949 and the installation of the Communist regime,
there have
been variations in the orientation of the Chinese Communist Party
towards the
family. The general direction has been, of course, a systematic
de-emphasis of
the traditional extended family. But the nuclear family itself,
although
recognized as a basic social unit, has at times become the subject of
revolutionary measures, notably during the Great Leap period in the
50's and
the Cultural Revolution of the 60's.[10] In
its variations, the general tendency of
the Chinese Communist Party has been to absorb the nuclear family
within the
commune. Considering the Chinese traditional extended family heritage,
this
policy points to an attempt by the communist authorities to achieve an
interesting metamorphosis.
One may surmise that
the
Chinese have been trying to circumvent the bourgeois nuclear family
phase. The
conversion from clan and kinship to people's communes may in fact be
easier than
first awakening nuclear family consciousness among couples and their
children,
then stripping them of their autonomy and passing the authority to the
commune.
The loyalty to the traditional patriarchal hierarchy is transferred to
the
ideological communal hierarchy with the parents serving as
value-forming agents
for that goal. The process is plausible if, as the Chinese intended,
the
communal organization is made the basic and sole structure of the
society and
"the function of the state will be limited to protecting the country
from
external aggression; and it will play no role internally.”[11] However, the implication that there may be
external aggression makes the likelihood of the final communal
arrangement
remote, because warding off external aggression implies national
institution
and planning which will strain the communes beyond their communal goals
and
make them part of the big whole.
If peace prevailed,
and the
communes were to become the total life experience of their members and
the sole
value-forming agency, they should become relatively small,
well-integrated
entities free from outside servitudes--and therefore without dependence
or
extensive interaction with the outside including a sovereign national
state.
Such a situation would revert us to conditions similar to those of
primeval
groups. In this situation, the revolutionary committees' and commune
managers'
ideological considerations should no longer be dictated from beyond the
commune, but shaped by the interests of their immediate communal
environment,
and their loyalty should be exclusively to the commune whose basic
nature will
become identical with a clan, with the difference that communes and
clans will
be at the opposite ends of the Marxian historical materialism spectrum.
To
follow the development from one to the other, we should indeed start by
identifying the clan as the early and sole value-forming agency
because, as we
noticed earlier, it is not necessarily the male-female couple which
plays the
predominant value-forming role. The family as a social unit has a more
general
connotation. The nuclear family of father, mother and offspring may
become a
dissociable part of a bigger entity: the extended family, itself
extending into
a clan. There, values are part and parcel of the group and the
identification
of the value forming agency poses no problem. The homogeneous and
monolithic
group and its values are a coherent and coincident whole.
In Chapter Three we
saw that
the evolution of the group brings about differentiations in
specialization and
in social strata, which in turn can bring about diversification of
interests
within the family, clan and kinship pattern, reducing its
all-encompassing
value-forming potentials. The son of the farmer may, for example,
become a
sailor and have life experiences not covered by nor tallying with the
value
pattern the family circle could provide. Thus, as the group grows in
complexity, to remain integrated, it will need additional value-forming
agencies. The agency which seems to have emerged to fulfill the added
value-forming needs at an early stage of social complexity is, in a
broad
sense, the religious institution. It became the promoter of beliefs and
the
custodian of the value system, superimposed on and interacting with the
family
and the clan. The institution of faith grew, of course, out of what was
already
there: the clan. The homo magus, the
witch doctor, the sorcerer, evolved into homo
divinans, the holder of the faith. Different cultures may have
emphasized
either the family or the religious institution as the dominant
value-forming
agency. For example, in China as compared to India the family played a
more
important role than the house of worship. But as anthropological
studies
indicate, at the earlier stages of social evolution, family and
religious
institutions became everywhere the principal value-forming agencies.
What is striking in
this social
evolution is the extent to which the social hierarchy and structure
have
entrusted the inculcation of values to the family and the
institutionalized
belief. Looking back at our earlier discussions, we may trace certain
paths of
convergence leading to this social phenomenon. Among the basic human
drives
discussed in Chapter Two, we can discern variations permitting us to
identify
some of those drives as more material and functional (the physiological
and
biological drives), some as more dynamic (the drives for domination,
excitement, game and challenge) and some as more oriented
towards social rationales (the drives for freedom,
justice and order). Further,
there are some drives which qualify more aptly as affectional and
nonrational.
They are those which complement the physiological needs for contact
comfort or
security and turn into needs for "love," attention, respect,
recognition,
approval and psychic reinforcement. There is also the drive to search
for and
fear the unknown, whose very nature and whose extension beyond the
known leads
to the nonrational. It is the essence of all religion to explain the
inexplicable: creation, death and what lies beyond. We saw in Chapter
Three
that the affectional and the nonrational were dimensions of group
relationship
interacting and merging with functional and rational dimensions to
create and
provide bases for values. It is then understandable to find the
institutions
which envelop and claim these affectional and nonrational dimensions,
namely
family -- clan -- and religion, as the primordial value-forming
agencies. As the
basic texture of the society, they not only perpetuate its value system
but
reflect it. They are not only value-forming agencies but values, and
each
upholds in its teachings the validity of the other. Faith permeates the
family,
and the religious institutions uphold the sacredness of the family and
the
honor of parenthood.
The family, having the
first
natural access to the fresh mind of the child, can generally inculcate
him with
such dimensions necessary for social life as obedience, deference,
cooperation,
"correct" sexual behavior and class consciousness. In most cases, the
family can provide a better evaluation and dosage of reward and
punishment than
can other social institutions. The long weaning and rearing provide the
appropriate setting to exploit the individual's imitative potentials
and to
apply repetitive methods of control and training, inculcating social
symbols
and rituals, feeding and orienting the child's imagination, impulses
and
drives. By appropriate conditioning and reinforcement, by authoritative
yet
affectionate imperatives such as "this is the way to do it," or
"you should not do that," the parents give the child a set of
unquestionable values, the acceptance of which prepares the individual
for
adherence to the belief system and the social and political authority
structure. The family further provides for the child the means of
communication
with his peers, who also play a strong value-forming role because of
their
similitude attraction and kindred qualities.
The complementary
roles and
tendencies of male and female not only lend themselves to satisfying
the
different dimensions of the child's needs, but also provide outlets for
the
adults' drives. Much of the parents' drives for domination, excitement
and
challenge, and their conservative and possessive drives, are combined,
tempered
and channeled for family responsibilities and the benefit of the social
structure. Depending on the culture and the individual nature, the man
may be
more reckless, free from filial and familial bonds. The female may be
socio-psychologically conditioned for motherhood and may develop
conservative
and possessive tendencies out of the biological experience of pregnancy
and
childbirth. The two -- male and female -- once combined, become
predictable and
responsible social units. The social authority structure
recognizes and upholds that responsibility.
The religious
institution picks
up its value-forming role from within the family. Drawing on the
dispositions
developed for acceptance of unquestionable values, it provides the
unanswerable
questions about the beyond with unquestionable answers, on the basis of
which
further values are passed on to the member of society. Devout
conviction
complements filial affection and respect. Belief becomes an important
factor in
the recognition of the peer group, whose adherence to the religious
institution
validates and reinforces its value
structure. As we shall see in Chapter Eleven, belief in divine omnipotence, combined with filial
piety, provides for the acceptance of and submission to the supremacy
of the
social and political hierarchy.
*
*
*
The coherence of the
value-forming roles of family and church with the social structure
depends, of course, on the
homogeneity of the society. That is why we examined the family and the
church
anthropologically at the primeval stage. When the society becomes
heterogeneous, family and religious institutions may be less integrated
within
the social system, in which case they will lose their exclusivity as
value-forming agencies. The social framework will then provide grounds
for the
competition of the different institutions and agencies involved. It
develops
into a complex beyond the original clan where the warriors, the elders
and the
shamans were components directly bound together in kinship ties. If one
of
these components has been instrumental in the group's social evolution
and has
acquired a prominent position in its hierarchy, it will want the
value-forming
agencies to inculcate the social values favoring its prominence, while
the
component itself (the emergent power structure emanating from warriors,
elders
or shamans) will want to operate beyond the confines of those agencies.
Indeed,
it must be able to expand its base of operations if it is to claim
political
sway beyond its own kinship ties; and it should identify itself with
controls and
interests distinct from the power of the custodians of the faith
(unless it is
the custodians of the faith who have secured secular power for
themselves, like
the priests of the Sumerian temples in Mesopotamia some 5,000 years
ago, or the
Church in the Vatican).
The heterogeneous
society will
reduce the functional attributes of the family and make different
demands on
family members. The patriarchal or matriarchal extended family or clan
will no
longer be the group's sole and total identifiable texture. The family,
no
longer the exclusive depository of the group's authority nor the direct
recipient in the distribution of tasks and prerogatives, may itself
feel the
discrepancies of social redistribution. If the parents' expectations
remain
unfulfilled, this may be reflected in the family's value-forming
processes, and
the family may create a spirit of resistance and challenge to the power
structure, providing a basis for social change. If this trend becomes
prevalent, the power structure, to maintain itself, may try to alienate
the
younger generation from the family through other value-forming agencies.
As for the
institutionalized
belief, by virtue of its inherent potentials for control (particularly
over the
soul) it will lay claim to social power. And if it does not already
control the
secular authority; it will rival it. Thus, the belief institution may
form
values not always coinciding with the interests of the political
secular
authority. The Christian church was not conceived by St. Augustine and
St. Thomas
purely and simply to support the ruling system, but also to check on
it. As
history witnesses, this trend has shaped most of our societies up to
the modern
age. From the conflict of Pharaoh Amenophis IV with the priests of
Amon-Re in
1372 B.C., to the Bismarckian Kulturkampf
against the Vatican Council's proclamation of the "dogma of papal
infallibility" in 1870, the issue has remained the same. Thus, with the
society growing in heterogeneity, relationships between the
socio-political
secular powers, the family/clan and the institution of faith evolve,
engendering at times (and often at the same time) cohesion and
coherence or
conflict and rivalry, stimulating the development and diffusion of new
value-forming patterns.
III.
Family, Church and Education
The new value-forming
patterns
in the heterogeneous society evolve from within the old premises. From
within
the family, the clan and the belief institution grows another
value-forming
agency which, sooner or later, can be identified as the instructional
and
educational institution. In its early stages the heterogeneous society
while
creating specializations beyond primeval forms, will nevertheless
depend
greatly on family, clan and kinship to provide training for skills,
crafts and
professions from one generation to another. This functional attribute
of the
family will be different from what it was at the primeval stage, when
the unit
was self-contained and virtually self-sufficient at the subsistence
level.
There, as we saw, every segment of the clan was identical in its
functions with
another segment, with every man, woman and child doing more or less
what every
other man, woman and child did within the clan. In the early cumulative
economy, families diversify their specializations. The carpenter's son
likely
follows his father's profession but has to depend on the butcher for
his meat.
Professional training in this context refers to social functions and at
first
sight may seem to carry no value-forming potentials. We need to take a
closer
look at its evolution, because as it evolves, its value-forming
potentials
become more apparent.
As the heterogeneous
society
grows more complex, expands and provides greater mobility, weakening
family
ties, especially those of the extended family, the passage of
professional
know-how from one generation to another shifts beyond the family.[12]
Learning a trade, whether from a father or from a master, becomes a
matter of
apprenticeship distinct from the rudimentary experiences and
affectional
securities provided by the family. This shift brings about an identity
among
the members of the same profession which, beyond the functional process
of
professional training, creates a community of outlook and provides for
affectional relationships and value-forming possibilities. At the
traditional
stages such relationships develop into brotherhoods, corporations and
guilds.
While these associations will have different types and degrees of
impact on
their members, they all carry the basic germ of common interests
which, as we noticed in Chapter Four, are essential in
forming social values. In that sense, they provide the historical link
and the
social dimension complementing the tribe and the interest groups. The
guilds of
medieval Europe were not only professional associations but developed
their own
moral codes And norms of conduct. The contracts of indenture passed
between the
master and the parents of the apprentice were not confined to teaching
a craft,
but placed the master in loco parentis--in
the place of the parents. He was responsible both to teach the
apprentice a
skill and to look after his welfare and moral education.[13]
Parallel to the
evolution of
professional training grows a traditional education centered around the
belief
institutions. The doctors of
faith -- whether doctors because they have evolved from the witch
doctors or
because they promote the "doctrine" -- will be called upon and will
claim to teach the "truth." The truths which the doctors will be
asked to impart will support both practical and moral purposes of
social life.
As distinct from its role as the house of worship, depending on the
complexities of the social structure, the institution of faith
inculcates the
young with the abstract thoughts and moral premises needed for social
order. It
also produces scribes who, by their knowledge of literature and
grammar, by
writing and recording, facilitate commercial business and the business
of
government. This pattern of social evolution varies with different
cultures,
depending upon their particular fermentations and dynamics and the
sequence of
events to which they are exposed in time and space.[14]
In traditional and
agricultural
societies, where change is slow, the economic and technical
specializations are
comparatively few, and most of the population is engaged in farming,
the
possibilities for the propagation of knowledge remain limited. Also,
the number
of people exposed to systematic education is comparatively small and
generally
selective on the bases of filial, professional, belief and class
standards.[15] It is noteworthy that certain social
conditions seem conducive to the growth and autonomy of secular
education as a
distinct value-forming agency, and that without them the secular
education
prematurely instituted tends to gravitate around the more primeval
value-forming agency of religion. For example, while Confucius and
early
Confucians advocated and practiced education free from supernatural
dogma, the
Chinese educational system fell back under the influence of the belief
systems
(although those systems in China were not as centralized, dogmatic and
potent
as medieval Christianity in Europe and did not totally absorb the
secular
educational practices).[16] A later current for systematized secular
education in China during the Sung period (960-1279 A. D.) was more
successful
and longer lasting because China had evolved into a comparatively more
urban
and bourgeois society, with a centralized and bureaucratic government.[17] It was not that the Chinese society was
liberated from religious beliefs, which indeed the Sung also upheld,
but that
concurrent with the premises of belief and the supernatural, the
secular
education acted as a value-forming agency in its own right and provided
moral,
ethical and social standards for a large segment of the Chinese middle
and
upper classes.[18]
In Europe secular
education
developed towards autonomy as a value-forming agency centuries later
than it
did in China. The church's preeminence as a value-forming agency during
the
dark ages of Europe encompassed education and inhibited the advancement
of
scientific learning. Even philosophical thought had to fit the
religious mold.
This religious hegemony was taking place on a continent which had seen
the days
of Aristotle, Plato, Seneca and Cicero. Otherwise, besides the Chinese
experience, in other parts of the world the search for the unknown
generally
combined the justification of the supernatural with philosophical
inquiry,
conditioning the latter by the former.[19] In
Europe, the Christian church became
preponderant because it was in a position to fill the political vacuum
created
by the collapse of the Roman Empire. If the church did continue to
dominate the
European scene for centuries, it was because European social
development and
political conditions were at the level of a traditional culture. We
noticed
earlier that while the social power and authority of the state depended
on the
belief structure, the latter also rivaled the former for social
control. In the
particular case of Europe in the earlier days of the Middle Ages, both
the
Christian religion and the emerging secular power of the northern
barbaric
tribes were alien importations in relation to the Graeco-Roman cultures
of
antiquity. But the church could claim an earlier Roman heritage, thus
commanding the respect of the secular powers it converted to
Christianity.
By the eleventh
century,
however, the secular powers of Europe, having developed their own
identity and
weary of the ever-increasing claims of the popes to temporal as well as
spiritual rule, welcomed conditions that would counterbalance the power
of the
church. These conditions, which culminated after five centuries in the
Renaissance and the Reformation, were economic, social, political and
intellectual, in many ways comparable to those of the Sung period in
China but
with later dramatic technical and industrial consequences catapulting
Europe
into the modern age. Central to our discussion here is the re-emergence
of
philosophical thought beyond the confines of religion, enhancing the
development of educational institutions as autonomous value-forming
agencies.
The early challenge to
the
Christian church's monopoly as value-forming agency took the general
form of
legal contentions and jurisdictional conflicts. A combination of
Germanic Volk laws with Roman law was gradually
being developed and practiced by the secular monarchs, corroding the
ecclesiastic authority.[20] In the spirit of this new revival of
Germanic customs, blended with the pre-Christian Roman legal concepts,
the princes
of the empire came to claim the churches of their realm--their Landeskirche--more and more as an
integral part of their political domain. Their patronage did not stop
at
providing for the material existence of a church but extended to its
administration
and control.[21] In this rivalry for power, the secular had
to meet the challenge of the church, not so much on theological grounds
but in
the field of jurisprudence. Ever increasing numbers of Cardinals were
trained
jurists, equipped with the know-how of government. In a way the state
was
forced to educate itself to cope with the omniscient spiritual power.
The
secular sovereigns thus tended to call more on lawyers and lay civil
servants
than on clerics supplied by the church to fill government offices.
These
bureaucrats had to be trained outside the church. Thus, the University
of
Naples became the first European university to be established by a
royal
charter, instituted by Frederick II in 1224 to train state officials.[22]
The
Philosopher
Parallel to this
evolution, new
dimensions were developing within the church itself. The study of Greek
philosophy, which Europe came to rediscover through Moslem thinkers
like
Avicenna (980-1037) and Averroes (1126-1198), flourished, blending the
theological tenets of such great scholastics as Albertus Magnus
(1193?-1280)
and St. Thomas (1225-1274) with Aristotelian logic. The introduction of
Aristotelian philosophy into theological thinking, however, itself
contributed
to the gradual loosening of the tight jacket of Christian orthodoxy on
philosophic thinking. With the competition between the secular princes
and the
papacy for power and authority, and the new philosophical dimension
injected
into theological thinking, European scholars found greater room for
critical analysis
and learning beyond the teachings of the church. It was within this
enlarged
context that the new thoughts of such scholars as Dante (1265-1321),
Marsiglio
of Padua (1280-1343) and William of Ockham (1290?-1349) gradually
provided
grounds for scientific inquiry, distinguishing the personality of
"educational institutions."[23] The nominalism of William of Ockham reversed
the scholastic synthesis of science and faith of Albertus Magnus and
St. Thomas
and suggested a distinction among philosophy, theology and the
scientific
approach. Basing itself on experimentation and legal positivism, it
carried the
germ of empiricism.[24] By the fourteenth century, most of the
universities that flourished in Germany, although Christian in
orientation and
spirit, had been established by secular princely or city charters,
indicating
the loss of the church's monopoly on education.[25]
The philosophic
emancipation
accompanied other dimensions of social change. The expansion of cities
and
commerce brought about a larger bourgeoisie. The appeal
to laic and non-cleric civil service by the European courts
enlarged the bureaucratic class. Once they became literate, these
classes
called for further literary and
artistic stimulation. The vernacular began to be used in literature. In
France,
Villehardouin (died c. 1212) wrote the first vernacular history, Conquest of Constantinople. The French
romances of the time, such as the Roman de la Rose of William
of Lorris,
taken up by Jean de Meung, were suggestively erotic and bourgeois.
Dante wrote La
Vita Nuova and the Divine Comedy in the Tuscan vernacular,
and he
defended writing in the vernacular in his De Vulgari Eloquentia,
written
in Latin. The attenuation of the church as the dominant pole of
attraction
permitted the development of new perspectives taking into account man's
point
of view. Thus flourished humanists such as the Florentines Petrarch
(1304-1374)
and Boccaccio (13131375). The humanist movement spread rapidly across
Europe
where, particularly in Germany, it developed along with the traditional
teachings within the universities and led the way to pedagogical
studies
concerning the development of the individual, culminating in the strong
plea of
Erasmus (1467-1536) for more schools and the popularization of
education. We know
of the influence that the thoughts of Erasmus had on Luther and the
later
evolutions of the Reformation. It was indeed after the Reformation that
the
educational institutions and philosophic thoughts became substantial
value-forming agencies in Europe. Komensky (or Comenius, 1592-1670),
the Czech
churchman (and nationalist), did for education what Galileo had done
for
astronomy, recognizing the principles of education rather than blind
faith as
man's guide to the labyrinth of the world. All this was accelerated
with the
improvement of the printing press by the early fifteenth century.
However, we must put
in the
right perspective the development of education as a distinct
value-forming
agency in the high middle ages and after. The social currents
contributing to
this development did not, strictly speaking, emanate from the masses
who, we
must remember, remained basically rural. In their refinement, all these
evolutions touched more directly the limited, higher stratum of
European
society. Philosophical inquiry germinated within the church with the
revival of
the Greek classics. In the conjuncture of temporal and spiritual
conflicts, it
found favorable patrons among the aristocrats
and the growing bourgeoisie and bureaucracy who encouraged its
pedagogic orientations
for social purposes. Philosophy begot pedagogy, yet it was the church
that
claimed its spiritual fatherhood, and it was mothered by the secular
powers and
the emerging bourgeoisie and bureaucracy. While the ensuing educational
institutions provided appropriate grounds for philosophical and
scientific
inquiry, they were at the same time regarded as agencies to promote the
interests and values of the various segments concerned. The fact that
these
interests and values did not always coincide was, of course, an
inspiration and
a challenge for philosophy and science. As mentioned earlier, the
church and
the aristocratic rulers did not always see
eye to eye. It was within the centers of higher learning that
the
problem was acknowledged and studied in depth. Despite the small
numbers which
philosophy then touched, it had nevertheless a great impact, for those
it
touched were those who counted. In the following centuries, it was
within
philosophic and scientific circles that the impending conflicts between
aristocracy
and bourgeoisie, proletariat and bourgeoisie, bourgeoisie and
bureaucracy were
first diagnosed.
This process of
philosophic and
scientific inquiry which bases itself on the analysis of facts,
experimentation
and reasoning (in short, the process of thought as opposed to the
uncritical
learning and acceptance of established values) can, of course, carry
germs of
change unfavorable to the dominant and current value system. The
established
social order, or rather its weightier part, can then rightfully resent
and
distrust the unruly and uninhibited tendencies of the intellectuals. In
other
words, within the educational
process we may distinguish two dimensions. The first is one which the prevailing order patronizes
as an extension and elaboration of the value-forming and training by
the
family, the guild and the church; the other, both cause and consequence
of the
first, will be inquiry for further knowledge, to improve life and to
explore
the unexplored. In general terms, this second dimension is
philosophy--the love
of wisdom. The different segments of the prevailing order may use this
dimension as a weapon in their social conflicts, but only in so far as
it
advances their cause. Sometimes the aim may be the total usurpation or
annihilation of the adversary, such as the struggle of the militant
proletariat
against the bourgeoisie. The intelligentsia in this case is given free
course
to pave the road and justify the final victory of the revolution, and
then is
put again into the mold of the ruling order, as in the case of the
Soviet
Union.
Sometimes, however,
the
contending power sectors are symbiotic and use the intelligentsia only
to
redistribute power without endangering each other's existence. This has
been
the usual pattern of social conflicts and the role of the
intelligentsia in the
Western world since the French Revolution. The fine line of social
control over
philosophic and scientific thought and its influence on the course of
events
is, of course, difficult to draw during periods of crisis, and at times
may get
out of the hands of the contending segments of the social order. This
was the
case, for example, of the French Revolution. The influence of the Philosophes had gone beyond what the
"Enlightened Despotism" of Louis XVI had intended and the bourgeoisie
contended. It took the aristocracy, the bourgeoisie and the church
years to
re-establish the simili-order of pre-revolution. But the irreparable
damage had
been done and a new social consciousness had been created, setting the
tone for
the political upheavals of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries and
eventually changing the very political texture of European society.
But it is in the
nature of
philosophic and intellectual inquiry, as its historical evolution and
social
dynamics attest, that it can inspire and influence the power structure without becoming it. Love of wisdom, in
its pure state, is not socially functional. It must be patronized by
the
functionally powerful segments of the society to become operative. That
is why
great political thinkers often dedicated their philosophic works to
princes of
state and church--not always to those whose rule corresponded to their
inclinations, but to those whom they hoped to change. And, indeed, they
were
patronized by those who had a hand on the reins of power. Philosophy,
in its
profound essence, does not patronize its own application, and the
socially
effective patron does not philosophize. To the extent that the one does
the
other, he ceases to be the one. To the extent the philosopher-king is a
philosopher, his kingly functions are carried out by others. Asokas do
not
perpetuate themselves,[26]
and the meditations and the practices of Marcus Aurelius were worlds
apart.
The
Pedagogue
I have insisted on the
pure and
essential stages of philosophy because it is there--in the search for
wisdom
(for the love of wisdom)--that philosophy is not socially functional.
Otherwise, the social order does pick up and convert the findings of
philosophic, scientific and intellectual inquiry into practical tools.
Within
the educational institutions, to separate these two dimensions (facts
and
values, skill-training and inquisitiveness, information and
inspiration) and
isolate them from one another is difficult. Once learning in itself is
recognized as a value and the process of learning and inquiry is
initiated,
limits to it must justify themselves within those premises. Education
generates
itself from within by the interaction of the two philosophic and
pedagogic
dimensions and the essential interaction of the peer group. That is
precisely
where the value-forming power of education resides. In abstraction,
that part
of education which is empirical and informative may not be considered
value-forming. But what is empirical and what is informative?
Empiricism itself
may be a principle of behavior and hence become a value. So may the
possession
of information. When the master shows the disciple how to hold the
chisel or
connect the wires or multiply 2 x 2, he not only passes on know-how,
but
commands respect (at least he should), and more often than not he
imparts
values by creating predispositions in the learner to see things from a
particular angle. As for the peer group within the educational
institution, not
only does it have influence through general exposure, but it also
affects the
learning behavior of its members.[27] Both
teachers and students in the
educational environment are led to embrace their peer group standards
of
learning and inquiry.
Educational
institutions thus
become value-forming agencies in their own right, promoting, together
with the
other value-forming agencies, the prevailing social values, but also
contrasting with and influencing them. The teacher receives the impact
of a
family and .a religious, mythical or ideological pattern, but what he
teaches
does not necessarily mirror the values of those institutions. He may
teach the
theory of evolution, conflicting with the dogma of the church, and be
tried for
it, as Scopes experienced in Dayton,
Tennessee, as late as 1925.
IV. New
Churches: Ideological and Mythical Systems
The Scopes trial,
however, was
not only a challenge between the two value-forming agencies of church
and
education. It also engendered a clash of the old and the new in
beliefs, myths
and ideologies. At about the time when the Einstein-Friedmann
relativistic
theories of cosmology--the Big Bang--were elaborated, Clarence Darrow,
the
famous Scopes defense attorney, made William Jennings Bryan, former U.
S.
Secretary of State who had invested all his energies in the
prosecution, testify
in the Dayton court that the whale swallowed Jonah, that Joshua made
the sun
stand still, and that the world was created in the year 4004 B. C.[28] At issue was the cultural evolution of the
Western world since the Renaissance and Reformation.
The inquiry injected
by the
revival of Greek philosophy into theology followed the arduous path
between
curiosity and conformity to reach the conclusions of Copernicus
(1473-1543),
Kepler (1571-1630), Galileo (1564-1642) and beyond, to the rational
thinking of
Descartes (1596-1650). Up to then the Augustinian postulate had
prevailed--believing before understanding. Galileo demonstrated that
what was
believed in, was not necessarily true. Once it was realized that the
premises
of belief may be false, the alternative was to base man's understanding
on
reason.[29] Descartes in France, Hobbes (1588-1679) in
England (although they did not always agree with each other) and others
were
labeled atheists, but Christians were no longer burning heretics at the
stake.
With the philosophic and scientific heritage of the seventeenth
century, the
experimental method initiated by Francis Bacon (1561-1626), the
deductive logic
of Descartes, and Newtonian discoveries based on experimental
rationalism, the
eighteenth century was set to become the Age of Enlightenment. The
rational
observations of the "enlighteners," generally more rational in France
and more observational in England, kept eroding the premises of the
established
church, sometimes inadvertently, other times by design.
Already at the turn of
the
century, John Locke (1632-1704) not only championed the idea of
toleration but,
in his Essay on Human Understanding
(1690), subjecting thought itself to experimentation and observation,
concluded
that ideas originated not in the soul--and by extension God--as
Descartes
believed, but in the senses. This sensualism developed into
eighteenth-century
utilitarianism. Claude Adrien Helvetius (1715-1771), who advanced the
idea that
men were inclined to maximize their pleasures and minimize their pains,
and who
influenced the philosophical work of Bentham, also claimed to have
proved that
God did not exist.[30] Along with French rationalism went David
Hume's (1711-1776) empiricism and skepticism about God[31]
and the flourishing schools of materialism and utilitarianism. Reason
and
empirical observation questioned God. The materialists reduced man's
concerns
to the palpable and "freed" him from abstract and metaphysical
speculations.[32] God was ceasing to be an answer and was
becoming a question. Then what was the answer?
We saw earlier that
religious
institutions appeased man's anxiety and, by inculcating him with faith
in God,
provided him with a sense of purpose which became instrumental in his
elaboration of norms and social and political organization. Since some
process
of value-crystallization is needed to provide man with purpose and
order, when
one value system fails, another should replace it. Reason, while
weakening the
foundations of religious institutions, was providing grounds for
another
value-crystallizing process, namely ideology. Historically, this brings
us to
the distinction we made earlier between the different crystallization
processes. While it was at the end of the nineteenth century that the
term
"ideology" was coined, we must be cautious in assuming that with the
advent of the age of reason in Europe, the belief institutions were
replaced as
value-forming agencies by ideological institutions.
Reason and empiricism
were not
always cozy corners for all the philosophical thinkers of the
eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries. One cannot leave the beyond alone simply because
one
cannot observe it or conceive it by reason.[33] There
grew schools of thought which, not
satisfied with the hard, cold facts of rationalism and not content with
the
pre-rational premises of religious faith, conceived of a beyond which
man could
project, sometimes to irrational dimensions, from within himself: the
abstract
dimensions which could be made godly and willful through feelings and
power of
spirit. The Romantics and idealists saw in man the possibilities of
realizations beyond the dissectable, mechanical and organic man of the
rational
and empirical scientists. Carlyle (1795-1881) saw in man the hero;
Nietzsche
(1844-1900) the superman; and beyond man, Herder (1744-1803) and Fichte
(1762-1814) saw the greatness of the nation; while Hegel, still further
beyond,
conceived of the "Idea of the world mind." These ideas, which
justified breakthroughs beyond the rational restrictions of historical
and philosophical
facts, later inspired the myths for modern value-crystallization, as
discussed
in Chapter Five.
Thus, with the waning
of vigor
in religious institutions--more in some societies, less in others--the
ground
was laid for new value-forming agencies. The process, although rapid in
historical context, was gradual. At first, ideologies such as socialism
or
myths conducive to nationalism did not represent organized institutions
(compared to the degree to which the church was organized). They were
fluids
running through the different social fibers, transmitted by the
existing social
structures: family, educational institutions and peer groups. New
value-forming
agencies based on myths and ideologies emerged in the heterogeneous
modern and
industrialized societies, as did religious institutions based on
supernatural
belief and faith from within the primeval groups when these groups
evolved into
communal and traditional patterns. Neither ideologies and myths, nor
the
institutions inspired by them were exactly new. Communism and socialism
were
outgrowths of capitalism which had itself been preceded by
mercantilism. As for
the institutions which we can identify in general terms as
associations,
pressure groups and parties (which serve to different extents as
value-forming
agencies for myths and ideologies), they were the ever-present
ingredients of
heterogeneous social textures. What was new about them was the
value-forming
magnitude of institutionalized myths and ideologies in the modern
Western
context. That magnitude had different impacts and natures in different
cultural
settings. Nationalism or communism developed differently in Great
Britain,
Germany or Russia.
Up to the end of the
eighteenth
century, the ideologically militant and missionary party was not
developed,
although its ingredients were there. In his essays on parties, David
Hume lists
those which are based on personal
ties, reflecting the affectional dimensions of kinship and friendship,
and
those founded on some real difference
of sentiment or interest, of which the most extraordinary are the
"parties
from principle, especially abstract
speculative principle,...known only to modern times" and, despite their
idealistic claims, often disguising "factions of interest."[34]
Hume had on his mind, notably, the Whigs and the Tories, political
factions
formed in the British Parliament in the seventeenth century,
respectively
opposing and supporting the royal court on questions of principle
which, as we
shall discuss in Chapter Eleven, were also inspired by particular
interests.
But these "parties from principle" were not as yet value-forming
agencies for the indoctrination of the masses. The new philosophic and
scientific approaches were discussed in informed circles which
sometimes became
structured. One of the most cosmopolitan of these was Freemasonry.
Originally a
brotherhood of masons in the middle ages, the organization developed in
England
in the early eighteenth century into a secret society, with
philosophical and
speculative tendencies. Its lodges spread quickly all over Europe where
the new
ideas of change were being studied and discussed. But because of its
secret
nature and lofty ideals, its elaborate symbols and rituals, and the
underdeveloped mass media, the movement was not destined for popular
activism.
Its adherents were mostly members of the upper classes, and--despite
papal
condemnation of the movement--a number of ecclesiastics. Such movements
were
instrumental in acquainting the sovereigns and the ruling classes in
Europe
with emerging ideas and inspiring their reforms and enlightened
despotism.
At the time of the
French
Revolution, the first attempts at organizing militant and ideological
associations and parties were made. Political clubs born of "societies
of
thought" (les sociétés de pensées),
which had been created as of the middle of the eighteenth century in
many
European countries, were meeting in the early years of the French
Revolution to
discuss affairs of state. Among the most militant were the Jacobin
clubs. These
clubs not only discussed political affairs, but watched the authorities
and
debated the reforms and policies of the Constitutional Assembly. The
enthusiasm
of the popular uprising and the liberty enjoyed by the press in the
early years
of the French Revolution supplemented the vigor of the political clubs,
which
did indeed serve as value-forming agencies. The role of these popular
clubs as
controls of the official authorities was recognized by the 1793
Convention, and
by 1794 they served as instruments of "the reign of terror" (the
period when commissioners of the National Convention who were sent to
the
French provinces collaborated with the Jacobins to suppress the
counterrevolutionaries, sometimes with great violence and terrorism).
However, the
experience was not
long-lasting, not only because of the historical conjunctures, but also
because
of the rudimentary techniques and means of mass indoctrination.
Uncompromising
factionalism cloaked in elaborate myths did not fit into the political
culture
of the French Revolution. "The cult of the Supreme Being," the
concept of the "republic of virtue" and the dynamics of "people
in revolution" which Robespierre used for his platform in the Committee
of
Public Safety (Comité de Salut publique)
in 1794 did not provide a well-rounded ideology which the revolutionary
committees and Jacobin clubs supporting him could oppose to their
adversaries,
nor sell to the Paris commune and the French workers as a package.
There was no
centrally organized party or disciplined hierarchy with a declared
ideology to
lead the clubs and the revolutionary committees. Nor were the means and
media
of communication yet developed for the ideological and mythological
agitation
and propaganda. That took the whole of the nineteenth century,
culminating in
the spectacular performances of the Fascist and Nazi parties in the
twentieth
century.
The economic, social
and
technological upheavals of nineteenth-century Europe brought about
conditions
permitting new interest clusters and their convergence towards certain
myths
and ideologies. The concentration of population in industrial centers,
the
development of rail transportation and the improvement of printing
facilitated
the movement of ideas. By the middle of the century the process of
value-crystallization into an ideology representing a certain interest
sector
took recognizable form: that of the Marxian proletariat. The Communist Manifesto defined the
value-forming role of the organs representing different classes and
reserved
for the proletariat, once it took power, the task of educating the
other
classes into the classless society. The politically organized group
thus
supplemented family, church and education as a value-forming agency in
its own
right, heavily depending on the peer group as a point of recruitment
and convergence
of like-minded people.
All politically active
groups,
however, do not have equal claims and impacts as value-forming
agencies. The
value-forming potentials of an organization depend on several systemic
variables. One is the nature of its involvement; that is, whether its
stated
goal is to serve as a forum for a broad spectrum of interests, to
defend
certain interests or to promote particular values. (As discussed in
Chapter
Four, of course, interests and values are intertwined.)[35] Another variable is the extent to which the
group association (or party) claims to voice the views and values of
its
adherents or to form and mold those views and values. Together with
these
variables goes the organization's degree of openness to membership and
participation:
its recruitment policy, the possibilities of member participation in
decision-
and policy-making, and its indoctrinating machinery. The Federation of
British
Industries, the American Farm Bureau Federation or the American
Greyhound Track
Operators Association are not value-forming agencies in the same sense
that the
Communist parties in the Soviet Union and China are. Different
combinations of
the enumerated variables cover, notably, various classifications made
of
political parties.[36] For instance, parties claiming to represent
a broad spectrum and to voice the views and values of their adherents
have been
labeled broker, caucus, coalitional, indirect or mass parties, while
parties
aiming to form and mold their members, promoting particular values,
have been
called ideological, militant, missionary or class interest parties. We
shall
refer to .the activities of these parties within the political system
later,
notably in Chapter Fourteen. As for their value-forming nature,
obviously the
ideologically militant and missionary parties play a more overt role.
But even
associations, organizations and parties claiming only to represent
particular
or broad spectrums of interests have value-forming dimensions. The
trade union
mentality grows within the trade union as distinct from family, church
or
school. The social and political conditions which the existence of
these
organizations brings about, such as voting, campaigning and
electioneering, are
in themselves not only value-forming but also influential on the other
agencies
so far discussed.
The value-forming
potentials of
ideologically and mythically militant associations and parties were not
fully
exploited until they received the boost of modern mass media. Before
that,
propaganda required more initiative on the part of its audience even to
be
transmitted at all. They had to read the pamphlet or move themselves to
within
the limited range of the herald's, bard's, minstrel's or haranguer's
voice. In
the 1920's and 1930 's radio invaded the masses. Through its waves the
modern
political leader could move millions in the comfort of their homes.
V. Mass
Media
Signs and symbols,
words and
images, spoken, written or acted out, whether in personal contacts, in
conferences, or in books, newspapers, magazines, radio or television
serve in
different degrees as instruments and amplifiers of the value-forming
agencies
so far discussed. The medium used by the family is, nearly exclusively,
word of
mouth. The church has traditionally used word of mouth for the masses
and the
written word for its inner communication, with recent experiments using
radio
and TV. The educational establishment has emphasized the written word
and word
of mouth in that order; it has begun to use radio and TV recently and
may use
them more in the future. Political associations and parties use all
these media
but, depending on their environment, rely more and more on radio and
TV--more
on radio in the less developed countries, more on TV in the developed
countries. The choice as to which medium to emphasize thus has
something to do
with the nature of the value-forming agency. The extent to which the
media are
used of course, has also to do with the particular cultures,
particularly
political cultures. In a totalitarian regime with an ideologically or
mythically militant party in power, the media and their contents will
be
declared an extension of the political organization. The program of the
All-Russian Communist Party (Bolsheviks) of March, 1919, provided for
"development of the propaganda of Communist ideas on a wide scale and
for
that purpose the utilization of state resources and apparatus," which
meant, of course, control of the mass media. Under more fluid regimes,
the
contents of the mass media are not directly controlled by the state or
a party.
The media are left more or less open to reflect the different currents
within
the society. In countries like France and Great Britain, the government
controls and subsidizes the functioning of some of the media, such as
radio and
TV, but leaves control of their content to bodies more or less
independent of
direct, overt governmental control. In the United States, while the
media are
promoted as private enterprises, they are subject to certain laws, like
Section
315 of the Federal Communications Act of 1934 providing for equal time
for all
political platforms. Also, state and federal censorship and other
mechanisms
regulate some of their content.
So far we are assuming
that the
medium is only the medium, that the different media are simply channels
serving
the value-forming agencies we have discussed. This is obviously
simplistic. As
pointed out at the beginning of this chapter, the social, political,
economic,
cultural (ethical and aesthetic) flux of the society means values are
formed by
more than just the easily identifiable agencies. The media, then, are
also
media for transmitting these complex dimensions. The poet, the singer,
the
painter or the architect, though using the media, may not represent any
of the
agencies we have so far discussed. But even in a face-to-face, word of
mouth
situation in a family, the language and words used, the intonation of
the
voice--not always voluntarily and consciously--influence the
value-forming
processes. In other words, the medium influences the message. To what
extent
does it do so? McLuhan raised a good deal of controversy by affirming,
"The medium is the message."[37] Let us more moderately say, however, that
there are both the medium and the
message.
One way of
establishing the
media's impact as value-forming agencies is to compare their relative
importance in that role. Depending on their type and nature, the media
have
different impacts, ranges and audiences; some are more appropriate for
some
contents than others. John Crosby, then TV and radio critic for the New
York Herald-Tribune, remarked on the
relativity of the media in regard to the 1960 Kennedy-Nixon
presidential
debate.[38] At the time of the debate, he had listened
to the radio and felt that Nixon had scored better. He was surprised to
find
out the next day that the consensus favored Kennedy. A few days later
he viewed
the videotape of the debate and was amazed at how the TV advantaged
Kennedy.[39] The discrepancy in his judgment of Nixon's
and Kennedy's performances had to do with the additional visual
dimension of
the TV; Kennedy simply looked better. The TV debate had a significant
effect on
the electorate because by 1960 the television had become a mass
medium. The Kennedy-Nixon debate was viewed and commented upon
by a substantial sector of the voting population. The TV became a mass
medium
not only because of technological developments, but also because of its
appeal
to the public and the nature of the country's economy. Books, magazines
and
newspapers have long benefited from technological advances in printing,
but
they demand more concentration and effort on the part of their
audiences. A
greater percentage of the public is likely to be reached by radio and
TV
because the effort demanded for exposure is merely to turn a knob.[40] Had Nixon and Kennedy carried out their
polemics by articles in The Nation,
for example, even if there were greater discrepancy in the scores of
their
duel, it would have touched a different audience and not affected the
outcome
of the elections to the same degree as their TV debate.
The popular use of a
medium
also has to do with a country's economic and social development. The
American
general public, though literate, may not necessarily read as much as
the
general public in, for example, Sweden. According to the 1972
statistics, there
were 333 TV sets per 1000 population in Sweden as against 472 sets per
1000 in
the U. S. A. There were 515 copies of daily newspapers per 1000 in
Sweden as
against 314 in the U. S. A. Of course, the number of newspaper copies
is not a
decisive indicator about the influence of the newspaper as a medium of
information. I have seen the Indian villager read the newspaper front
to back,
and the Manhattanite rush out of the subway, buy the New
York Times, keep the classified section and throw the rest away.
The Western man's culture of accelerated and concentrated economic
effort,
whether in an office, in a factory or on a farm, may reduce his drive
for
concentrated reading.
Because of their
different
forms and potentials, one medium cannot totally replace another. They
appeal to
different audiences with different interests, goals and values. The man
who
wants to know Kantian philosophy will probably want to read it
directly, not
just see a program about it on TV. The written word, depending, of
course, on
whether it is in a popular magazine or a scholarly treatise, can deal
with a
subject in greater detail and be scrutinized more carefully by the
reader than
can TV or radio coverage of the same topic. The book is a docile
companion, yet
a stubborn interlocutor. It is the garden of dreams and the field of
imagination. The reader can make the world of the book according to his
own
image. He can choose his pace with the book, go back to its earlier
arguments
and debate with it. The book will not raise its voice, but neither will
it
change its mind -- printed black on white.
This brings us to our
more
direct concern about the value-forming role of the media. Our
examination of
the different impacts and audiences of the media so far shows us that
their
value-forming potentials vary, but it does not necessarily qualify them
as
value-forming agencies. Rather, at this stage of our inquiry, their
participation in the value-forming process seems to be passive. Indeed,
the
question to ask is: How does a writer come to write what he writes, who
decides
on the content of a book or a radio or TV program, and who wants it?
Who
decides that an article or book should be published or a program go on
the air?
Should we consider mass media as value-forming agencies while they are
really
just frames to be filled by people whose values have been shaped by
other
agencies? After all, Kennedy and Nixon were representing
the political values of their parties.
The mass media's
passivity in
forming values may best be illustrated in the totalitarian state, where
the
media are totally at the service of the political apparatus.
Paradoxically,
however, this same illustration can help us examine the independent
value-forming potentials of the media. For where the fiction of freedom
of
expression is officially subordinated to a myth or ideology, any
discrepancy
which may be discerned between the official structural
and overall content control of the media, and the actual
processing and presentation of the content, will indicate the
possibilities for
the mass media to play an original role in influencing their audience.
In
speaking of the mass media as shapers of values, let us then
distinguish among
structural control, overall content
control, and the actual processing
and presentation of the content.
Structural control of
the
media, reflecting the prevailing social, economic and political order,
can run
from total state control to regulated private enterprise management of
the
media. Total state control is structurally effective only to the extent
that
the total control of the social complex as a whole is effective. The
Soviet
state control of the media during the Stalin era was much more
monolithic than
after de-Stalinization in the early 1960's
when, while the media structures remained under state control, the
"liberals" managed to penetrate the cultural apparatus.[41] It is unthinkable that a Yevtushenko could
have recited "Babi Yar" in front of Stalin and gotten away with it,[42]
or that the outspoken Solzhenitsyn would have been spared from exile
for so
long under the old dictator, or that the "Samizdat"
(personally circulated pamphlets) could proliferate
in the Soviet Union as has been the case recently. Certain media, of
course,
because of their nature and technology, can be controlled more
effectively by a
faction in power. It is more difficult at present to transmit a
clandestine TV
program than to circulate an underground pamphlet.
When we look at the
structural
control of the media in the United States as compared to the
totalitarian
control in the Soviet Union, we notice that the basic democratic
liberties of
freedom of expression, of speech and of the press are conditioned by
the
realities of competitive free enterprise with its tendencies towards
conglomerates and monopolies. A newspaper, a radio or TV network under
competitive free enterprise abides by the same financial and economic
rules
that govern business: it needs a market and a profit. Thus, it must
have either
a sufficiently big organization to gather the information and sell
advertisements,
or be affiliated with a big outfit. The tendency, then, is towards
control of
the structure and organization of the mass media by big business.[43] The argument for structural and financial
supervision of certain mass media by the state in some European
countries has
been intended precisely to avoid their falling under the control of one
sector,
such as big business or a party with totalitarian tendencies. The
government-supported national autonomous organisms of radio and
television
engender, however, the potential of succumbing to the influence of
their
patron: the state.
Financial and
structural
control of the media, however, does not necessarily make the media
useful for
the ends of the controllers. For that, the media need an audience. In
the free
enterprise context, for example, in order to be profitable, the media
should
have a large enough audience to attract the advertisements constituting
their
main source of income. It is between their audience and their
advertisers that
the mass media should find the criteria for their operation and the
control of
their programs.
This brings us to a
.discussion
of overall content control. While in a free enterprise the structure
and
organization of the media are usually controlled by business, and while
the
main source of their income is advertising which also, in its
quasi-totality,
comes from business, there remains the need for an audience--a need
which
business recognizes and which conditions the content of the media's
information
and programs. From this point on, the controller of the structures of
the
media, whether it is the Communist Party of the Soviet Union or the
majority
share-holder of RCA or NBC, has to rely on the editors, reporters,
commentators
and all those who have made it their profession to run the show. The
final
purpose for printing a daily or a magazine is to have it read; for
creating a
radio or TV network, to have the set turned on. Thus, those who control
the
media's structure and organization cannot force their values on the
audience
(if they are different than those of the audience) without making them
palatable. Thus, the audience at least indirectly influences the
content.
Regular rating will permit the TV networks to adjust their programs to
the
audience's taste. The adjustment takes into account the social flux and
the
prevailing values--those of the audience and those of the owners and
advertisers of the network.
In principle, the
choices given
to the audience should not deviate from the values cherished by those
who
finance the existence of the media. NBC or CBS would not preach
communism, nor
would Pravda or the Soviet State Television preach capitalism. That
fact is, at
least in principle, understandable. In practice, however, the content
of mass
media does not strictly reflect the values of those who control their
structure. Beyond the compromise between the values of the controlling
business
and the tastes and values of the audience, there is the influence of
those who
provide material for and produce the content of the media. In the
heterogeneous
complex society, the media professionals who scrutinize the society for
the
materials they want to use will eventually develop their own angles of
vision
conditioning the content of their medium. The modern media's claims to
impartiality
may sometimes blur their value-forming role.
The impact and nature
of
content-controllers' influence varies from medium to medium. It is
probably by
looking at the written word, books, that we may more readily define the
valuational responsibilities and influences. The publishers control the
organizational and distributive business, while the private writer
provides the
content. Whether that content reflects the values of the structure
which makes
publishing possible or is geared to the taste of the readers, it is
usually
associated with the writer. He is the one who takes responsibility for
the form
and the philosophy presented and in most cases claims to advance unique
valuational dimensions which may--and often do--go against the values
of business
(including those which make publishing possible).[44] Of course, the organizational controllers of
publishing will set valuational limits on what will be published. In
the Soviet
Union, the Ministry of Culture and the Writers Union can decide whether
a book
is published. We know the fate of the works of Pasternak and
Solzhenitsyn. In
the West, the limits are laid by bourgeois values. The book should
sell. If it
may sell but offends certain social values, it has to wait until those
values
have evolved. The values often evolve, however, when business
compromises its
values by publishing what startles its audience, because the startling
subject
sells well. Thus, by writing the book, the author takes the first step
towards
transforming the prevailing values. There resides the value-forming
role of the
medium--the book, in this case. Novels of James Joyce, D. H. Lawrence
and Henry
Miller were first banned in the United States, but times changed and
they made
their way to the public.
Our look at the
creative work
of an author may enable us to realize the role and influence of those
who
prepare and produce the contents of other media. The journalist or the
radio or
TV editor may try to reflect the values of the power structure or of
the
masses, but he is also more deeply exposed to and involved in the
artistic and
literary works which supply material for his program, inspire him and
may
create in him new valuational dimensions. The mass media thus breed a
new
species of social and professional intelligentsia. The journalist
cannot, of
course, bluntly use the media as a platform for his own values. He has
to
compromise between what his financial or political bosses want, what
the
audience wants, and his own outlook.[45] The
stricter the structural control, as in
the totalitarian regimes, or the broader the popular rating, as in the
bourgeois democracy, the less the possibility for autonomous media
artistry.[46] It is interesting to notice, for example,
the breath of fresh air that sometimes blows over TV programming in the
United
States during the "black weeks" (the occasional periods when the
rating companies take time off).
The more integrated
the
society, where the structural and financial controllers of the mass
media, the
producers of the contents and programs, and the readers and viewers
share a
general pattern of values, the more the media serve as
value-reinforcement
agencies, as distinct from value-forming agencies.[47] It is during the periods of social change
and dynamism that the mass media may serve as autonomous value-forming
agencies, influencing the mainstream of social values. In such
situations, the
mass media can more easily look beyond the confines of other
value-forming
agencies. Some ingredients of the media which accelerate social change
may be
products of cultural interpenetrations. For example, Western movies
have had an
impact on the bourgeois classes of underdeveloped countries ever since
the
1930's and 1940's--an impact which played a role in loosening the
traditional
values in many underdeveloped countries, making way for acceptance of
change.
Indeed, the mass media
do more
than entertain and inform; and people try to control them not only to
sell
entertainment and information for a profit but also to exploit their
propaganda
and agitation potentials.[48] It is not only when a particular medium
plays politics that it exerts valuational pressure-because at least
then it
shows its colors.[49] It is when the media claim to entertain and
inform that they overtly agitate or covertly propagandize. In the
actual
processing and presentation, the content, the sequence, the range and
the
emphasis of the basic "what, where, when, why, how and who" can be so
manipulated as to carry a particular message with a given valuational
overtone.
The TV camera can emphasize the contents of a speech or rub in the
disruptions
in the audience. The radio journalist can read the news with a
sarcastic or a
respectful tone, and the journalist can tell tales between the
lines--or, as
editor, drown information in an unnoticeable corner or display it on
the front
page. All this can take place according to conscious planning, all the
way from
the actual presentation of reports and comments to overall content
controls and
beyond to structural control. But it also can and does take place
subconsciously
underneath the ripples of human communication.
The media, whether by
their
message in particular or their role in general, will, in the last
analysis,
have a decisive impact (negative or positive, depending on who is
evaluating
and the outcome) on their total social complex. In State
of Florida vs. Ronney Zamora (1977) the defense even tried to
put TV on trial for its negative value-forming effects on the
defendent, a
15-year-old youth who, allegedly intoxicated by watching too much
violence on
the tube, had robbed and murdered an 82-year-old neighbor woman.
Whether the
audience is the individual members of the society or the masses as a
whole,
what finally counts is what, where, when, why and how gets to whom. An
author
writes a book and throws her thoughts like seeds into the winds. The
author may
be Barbara Tuchman, and her book, The
Guns of August; it may be read by the President of the United
States and
influence his course of action.[50] On
a more massive scale, we may cite the
impact of the radio in Nasserian Egypt. The introduction of the radio
into the
remote villages and the new world thus opened to the isolated peasants
gave
them expectations unaccompanied by corresponding achievement incentives
or
provisions for their fulfillment. The result was frustration. As Lerner
stated,
Major Salah Salem, the Minister of National Guidance in the early days
of the
Egyptian revolution, concluded that it was impossible to convert an
"inert
and isolated peasantry into an informed and participant citizenry by
the mass
media alone."[51] But the media did do its own uncalled-for
value-forming. This is one of the more characteristic dimensions of the
mass
media compared to other value-forming agencies: Its impact is more
open-ended.
Family, church, education and parties, as they form our values, keep a
tab on
us. The mass media leave us more room for criticism, interpretation and
imagination.[52]
A factor which we
should not
leave unnoticed before concluding this section on the media as
value-forming
agencies is the role played by the peer group in the media context. The
peer
group influences its members on the choice of media, propagates the
media's
messages and serves as a supplemental source of information. The
individual is
likely to read the books and watch the TV programs that his peers read
and
watch, and he depends, to a large extent, on his peers to learn about
the
happenings of the world, and their interpretation.[53]
VI.
Family, Church,
Education,
Party, Media and Peers
Our examination of the
different value-forming agencies within the social complex has shown
how they
evolve from within each other and develop, mix, coexist and intertwine
to
contribute their particular value-forming shares. The political party
hardly
replaces the family (at least so far) and, as we saw earlier, even if
it had
totalitarian control, it would have to call on the family to instill
its
long-lasting influence into the child. The family registers, stores and
influences general social patterns in the long run. Because it
generally
embraces a few generations, it secures the continuity of social norms
and
values. Of course, generations influence each other both ways. But the
older
generation is usually the carrier of the more established norms. The
older
generation, which was once the younger generation, was influenced in
its own
time by new social approaches (including indoctrination by the power
structure
and authorities) and, through action and reaction with the old
generations of
its younger times, assimilated them into the pattern of socialization
which it
presents to the new generation.[54]
The church creates the
binding
supernatural dimension which other agencies do not provide. Even in
totalitarian states where the church's role is drastically reduced, the
need
for this binding force and some of its ritualization emerges in other
forms.
The Soviets had discouraged religious marriages, but when faced with
numerous,
unabashed divorces disrupting the social order, they not only passed
stricter
laws but also developed elaborate ceremonies to make marriage a unique
life
experience and sanctify its moral commitment. For example, Palaces of
Marriage
in Soviet cities provides a spiritual atmosphere for the unions
contracted, and
persons marrying for the second or subsequent time may not register
there.[55] The educational institutions, as already
discussed, provide for the knowledge and skill which in the complex
heterogeneous society other agencies cannot easily supply. They also
expose the
young to additional ethical dimensions beyond the more traditional
patterns of
family and church before they join the mainstream of social life.
Parties,
associations, factions and interest groups--in short, associational
affiliations -- not only supplement, through their ideologies and
myths, those
premises of the church which falter in the age of science and
technology, but
also provide forums and platforms for the diversities inherent in a
complex
modern society. The mass media provide channels of communication,
without which
the modern society would be paralyzed. Beyond that, mass media help
create the
patterns through which social complexities become identifiable and
ideas take
shape and flow into the social current.
Finally, a place
should be
reserved for the peer group as a value-forming agency. You may have
noticed
that in our discussion of every other agency we have pointed out the
peer
group's role within it. Because of the fluidity of its definition
(peers
meaning simply equals), the peer group can cut across agency lines,
combining
and amalgamating the characteristics and identifications of each agency
within
the individual who is influenced by them. Thus, in the context of any
single
agency, the individual may be identified as a peer to others on the
basis of
common characteristics each may have acquired under the influence of
other
agencies. If, for example, within the family peers are distinguished by
age and
sex, we may find that within the church, education or political
association,
the same distinctions serve as
bases of peer identification. Similarly, the values inculcated by the
church,
the level of education, the professional affiliation, the political
myth or
ideology can each provide for peer identification across the areas of
different
agencies.[56]
Of course, there is no
distinct
line between spheres of activities of the different agencies. In the
exercise
of their functions they overlap. In their
interactions and intertwinings they may support, supplement or supplant
each
other. We mentioned earlier the mutual support between family and
church, and
the interrelation of the church and the educational establishment. In
their
admixture, the different value-forming agencies feel each other's pull and push. There is, for example,
the "Mendelian law of politics," i.e., the inheritance of party
identification,
which apparently overlaps familial and associational affiliations.[57] Churches and political associations have had
a long history of interaction. In modern times the church has taken
sides with
different political tendencies and, despite their obvious rivalry with the faith, has promoted certain
myths and ideologies against others-choosing the least dangerous of the
evil
competitors. It was easier for the church to coexist with capitalist
free
enterprise than with communist totalitarianism which professed atheism.
The
mass media bring the church and the political associations into contact
with
their elements. They also provide the continuing education the
fast-moving
modern world needs beyond the walls of the educational institutions.
While the agencies as
a whole
promote the amalgam of values prevailing within the society, they do
not
necessarily support each other harmoniously. Each agency, in passing on
the
prevailing values to the group members, blends them according to its
own point
of view. Different agencies may sometimes have conflicting interests or
a lack
of synchronization because their value-forming processes have different
paces
and tempos. The family and church, for example, may lag behind the
educational
system and mass media. If a particular agency or social sector becomes
predominant, it may enhance or restrict the value-forming role of the
other
agencies. The ideologically militant Bolsheviks took over Russia in
1917
because the other value-forming agencies lagged behind. Sometimes the
enhancement or restriction of the role of certain value-forming
agencies by the
prevailing order may take drastic proportions. History has witnessed
book-burning practices from the legalists of China in the third century
B. C.
to the Nazis in the twentieth century A. D. Churches, temples and
synagogues
have been burned in the course of human history. Educational systems
have
suffered restrictions and regimentations by the church and political
powers,
and political associations have suffered suppression by dominating
powers,
whether religious or political. But when the forceful control of the
social
flux is exaggerated, a backlash or a revival of the suppressed
value-forming
agencies may occur, as happened with the family institution in the
Soviet Union.
The more there is
social
fluidity, the more the push and pull of the different agencies and
their free
interplay will determine their value-forming magnitude. For example, if
the
value-forming roles of family and church diminish within the highly
industrialized,
mobile and heterogeneous groups in the United States, it is not through
overt
suppression by any other value-forming agency, but due to the direction
of the
social flux. Going through the history of the different agencies
discussed, we
can discern an evolution in their order of magnitude as we move from
traditional to more modern societies.
Fig.
7.01
In the primeval
context the
sphere of family, clan and kinship covered the total value-forming area
and the
other agencies were not identifiable. If we were to illustrate the
magnitude of
each agency in comparison with others on a frequency distribution chart
giving
each agency a volume corresponding to the importance of its
value-forming role
within a given society at a given time, at the primeval group level,
the curve
will be totally skewed in favor of family, clan and kinship (Fig. 7.1).
Moving toward more
heterogeneous societies, we may find curves emphasizing family and
church and
later education in a traditional society. Of course, no precise curve
for any
particular society at any given time can be drawn without detailed
data--if
such data can be empirically collected. But the chart can indicate an
evolution
in the value-forming role of different agencies, going from the
prominence of
the family and church in traditional societies to that of political
institutions and mass media in modern societies. In this evolution,
educational
institutions could probably be represented as standing in the middle,
shared by
both traditional and modern societies. A curve for the Chinese Sung
Dynasty's
age of reform in the eleventh century, for example, may emphasize the
traditional value-forming agencies, while a curve for the present
Chinese
regime would emphasize the educational system, party and mass media.
Fig. 7.2
Similar trends are
traceable in
the West, from the medieval church and family to the age of TV. The
question
that arises is: How far can this shift in the skew of the curves
progress? Will
the modern age--as some have suggested, at least in the form of science
fiction--end up skewed at the far right, with the electronic media as
the sole
controlling agency inculcating man's values, beliefs, education and
political
consciousness? There are arguments for and against, depending on how
one views
the combination of technology with human nature. Technologically
speaking, in
some societies we are very fast getting there.
A study of human
nature may
also seem to lead to a conclusion favoring the possibility of total
control
through mass media. Exposure to the media in electronic form is a new
experience for man. The effects so far registered suggest a high degree
of
passivity to the electronic inroads on the part of listeners and
viewers and
their gullibility to sophisticated indoctrination. The new dimension
introduced
by modern electronic media is revolutionary not only in the
technological
sense, but also ethologically. Communication is a condition sine
qua non for the passage of values.
In order to be able to pass on values, the social agencies need to
communicate
with their members. We noted in the last chapter that, with our present
scientific knowledge, we believe that human communication--unlike that
of many
lower animals, which are equipped with instinctive and innate means of
communication--should take place within the social context, and its
means
should be given to the members of society through learning and
socialization.
Before the advent of the electronic mass media, the value-forming
process
needed direct human contact and warmth, for both the inculcation of
values by
word of mouth and initiation into the written word. The electronic mass
media
have expanded the human horizon for communication beyond the needs for
personal
contact and experience. If communication is so essential and if modern
electronic media can bring man a total dimension of communication, will
the
media not become the message? To ask this question is to overlook the
fact that
while man is their object, the media and the message are man's
subjects. It has
been a long time since Chapter Two when we discussed man in his own
right as a
political animal. In the chapters that followed, the social contexts
and
contents engendering man seem to have absorbed him and claimed his
total
delineation. Yet discussing symbols in the last chapter we saw, for
example,
that while the pattern of communication develops through socialization,
employing man's imitative qualities and the repetitive process of
assimilation
and accommodation, it is not a quid pro
quo registration of the symbols but their
adaptation to the individual organism, which in turn contributes
to the
symbolic creative process as it transmits the symbols along. Further,
the
symbolic complex carries variations characteristic of intergroup and
interagency cooperations and conflicts. It is hardly plausible that
within
these dynamics the medium can become the message. And that, of course,
as we
have seen, also goes for the other agencies. For the message and the
agencies
which carry it, although influential, themselves grow out of the social
flux, which is in turn made of men. To
paraphrase a famous saying, you can control all the people some of the
time;
you can control some of the people all the time; but you cannot control
all the
people all the time.
These final
observations call
for a reassessment of man's role within the socio-political complex
that has
emerged in the last chapters. In the last analysis, it is the nature
and
intensity of the interactions among members of society with various
social
agencies and institutions which enhance, solidify, rigidify or
attenuate the
different social control patterns. Our re-examination and reassessment
of man
and society will help us understand the patterns of authority and
political
structures which, within the socio-political complex, are more deeply
involved
in the elaboration of the legal norms complementing the moral and
ethical
values, which are more directly promoted by the value-forming agencies
we have
discussed in this chapter.
[1] For similar approaches see, for example, V. 0. Key, Jr., Public Opinion and American Democracy (New York: Knopf, 1961), pp. 291 ff. and Richard E. Dawson and Kenneth Prewitt, Political Socialization (Boston: Little, Brown, 1969), notably Part III.
[2] The early legal and religious recognition of family as a social institution in different cultures is striking. We saw the case of filial piety in Confucian China (supra, p. 52). In fact, filial piety was a legal obligation in China much earlier than the time of Confucius. In Legge's translation of The Shoo King, (The Shoo King, The Chinese Classics, Vol. III (London, 1865), p. 392.) we read of a Chou ordinance labeling as criminals "the son who does not reverently discharge his duty to his father, but greatly wounds his father's heart; and the father who can no longer love his son." The address to Osiris in the Egyptian Book of the Dead (2500 B. C.) includes the item: "I have not oppressed the members of my family." Article 195 of the Code of Hammurabi (1800 B. C.) reads: "If a son has struck his father, his hand shall be cut off"; and, "Honor thy father and thy mother" is among the Judeo-Christian Ten Commandments.
[3] S. N. Eisenstadt, From Generation to Generation (New York: Free Press, 1956), notably pp. 316-321.
[4] In a model constitution for the foundation of youth communes, the Soviet Komsomol, condemning a licentious sex life, said: "The sexual question can be correctly decided in one way only; steadfast and lasting marriage founded on love." Quoted in Klaus Mehnert, Youth in Soviet Russia (London: Allen & Unwin, 1933), p. 215.
[5]
A. S. Makarenko, The Collective Family: A Handbook for
Russian Parents; published in the Soviet Union as A Book for Soviet
Parents
(Garden City, N,Y.: Doubleday, 1967), pp. 27-28.
[6]
S.
Stroumiline, Pensees sur le
Communisme (Paris: Agence de Presse Novosti, Supplement a Etudes
Sovietiques, 178, 1963).
[7] A. Kharchev, "Once More on the Family," Pravda, 23 November 1966, traps. in Current Digest of the Soviet Press, 14 December 1966, p. 23. Kharchev's book Marriage and Family Relations in the U.S.S.R. (Moscow: Novosti, 1965) was one of the substantial and first attempts at a comprehensive study of the Soviet family. It is a good illustration of the Soviet concern to establish the family as a useful value-forming agency. See notably Peter Juviler, "Soviet Families," Survey, No. 60 (July 1966); Kent M. Geiger, The Family in Soviet Russia (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1968); and Paul Hollander, ed., American and Soviet Society: A Reader in Comparative Sociology and Perception (Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-Hall, 1969). This last work contains useful excerpts on the subject from Soviet authors.
[8] See, for example, Alex Simirenko, ed., Social Thought in the Soviet Union (Chicago: Quadrangle, 1969), and Urie Bronfenbrenner, Two Worlds of Childhood (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 1970).
[9] C. K. Yang, The Chinese Family in the Communist Revolution (Cambridge, Mass.: M. I. T. Press, 1959), pp. 5 ff.
[10] James R. Townsend, Politics in China (Boston: Little, Brown, 1974), pp. 188-194.
[11] "Resolution on Some Questions Concerning the People's Communes," Communique and Resolution of the Sixth Plenary Session of the Central Committee of the Communist Party of China (Peking: China Reconstructs, 1959), p. 14.
[12] See Ernest Burgess and Harvey J. Locke, The Family: From Institution to Companionship, 2nd ed. (American Book Co., 1953), notably p. 312.
[13] This pattern can be traced in the traditional stages of different cultures, such as the early Egyptian, Sumerian, Chinese and Persian. For the particular case of Europe, see for example P. Boissonnade, Life and Work in Medieval Europe (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, 1927); Henri Pirenne, Medieval Cities (Cambridge, Mass.: Princeton Univ. Press, 1925); Norman F. Cantor and Michael S. Werthman, eds., The Structure of European History, Vol. 2 (New York: Crowell, 1967). Our terms of reference will include training and apprenticeship arrangements within the framework of the mercenary soldiery and knighthood, chivalrous rules of conduct, and manorial courtly manners. See, for example, William Stearns Davis, Life on a Medieval Barony (New York: Harper, 1923); Sidney Painter, French Chivalry (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press, 1940).
[14] Archeological and historical evidence indicates that the general sketch drawn above was the pattern of early educational evolution in the Egyptian, Sumerian, Vedic and Hebrew cultures, where temple schools provided the basic social education, although later in China and Greece there seem to have developed educational systems more autonomous from the system of belief. Nevertheless, we should not forget that even the Pythagoreans, whose supreme Olympian was Apollo, the god of light and reason, had their Orphic doctrine for mystic union with the beyond, with its sacred texts and beliefs. At about the time of Pythagoras (sixth century B.C.) Confucius in China was emphasizing the role of education in social development.
[15] This is indeed the pattern which supplanted the Greek and Roman cultures of the Mediterranean and prevailed over Western Europe from the advent of Christianity to the Renaissance, but more particularly during the dark ages (between the sixth and eleventh centuries, when the church powerfully discouraged secular learning).
[16] The Confucian approach was the first attempt at a well-rounded education of the individual for social purposes, giving him the appropriate training for a job (government service) and initiating him with moral and ethical values: the li and ti. (For different connotations of Z2, see H. G. Creel, Chinese Thought from Confucius to Mao Tse-tung (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1953), pp. 29 ff.; and Michael Loewe, Imperial China (New York: Praeger, 1966), p. 96.) Yet, while the Confucian doctrine scorned the practice of divination and became the backbone of Chinese laic education and civil service for over 2,000 years, it did not escape the influence of the belief system. By Han times (202 B. C.-220 A. D.) Confucianism was attributed the authorship of the Book of Changes, an ancient diviner's manual, whose original version preceded Confucius by many centuries. See Creel, Chinese Thought, pp. 172; and James Legge's preface and introduction to the second edition of the I Ching: Book of Changes (New York: University Books, 1964; originally published in 1882).
[17] During this period there was a generalized use of the printing press, which made classical texts more accessible to a wider circle of scholars and thus provided more talents on which the civil service could draw for expansion. It also facilitated and went hand-in-hand with the commercial and technological advances of the time. While the techniques of printing were known to the Chinese much earlier, it was during the tenth century that the Sung government started making massive use of it. (Loewe, Imperial China, pp. 111-112.) Printing was used to produce bills of exchange and official banknotes needed for commercial exchange. The growing diversities in trade and manufacture and the complexities of government affairs gave rise to substantial bureaucratic, bourgeois and technological classes which enhanced the further development of educational institutions. In that context, the growing class of scholars was able to present a Confucianism greatly "stripped of its religious character, and left as an ethical system divorced from supernatural sanctions." Fitzgerald, China, p. 410.
[18] For an interesting collection of writings on the Sung period, see James T. C. Liu and Peter J. Golas, eds., Change in Sung China: Innovation or Renovation (Lexington, Mass.: Heath, 1969).
[19] From the Brahmanic schools of Taxila and Nalanda in the seventh century B. C. India to the later Islamic Madressahs of the Moslem world flourishing from Spain to India, grammar and logic, astrology and astronomy, arithmetic and geometry, medicine and alchemy were studied within the orbit of the prevailing religion. Not that they did not have their unorthodox scholars and philosophers like Avicenna, but they remained within a traditional setting where the social and political structures drew their identity from the religious fiber.
[20] Adolf Harnack, History of Dogma, author's 3rd ed. of 1893 (New York: Dover, 1961).
[21] Mulford Q. Sibley, Political Ideas and ideologies: A History of Political Thought (New York: Harper & Row, 1970), p. 201.
[22] Other universities were founded, although with the patronage of the church and the service of religious scholars, yet distinct from monastical education. The "Guild of Masters," recognized in 1170, provided the germ of the University of Paris, which was chartered in 1200. Cambridge was founded in 1209.
[23] When asked who should interpret the complexities of the scriptures, Marsiglio of Padua replied: "Its meaning is to be authoritatively given by those who have knowledge and wisdom in these things, the men of intelligence. In this respect ,...the University of Paris -- his own alma mater -- may have better insights and scholarship than the Bishop of Rome himself." Ibid., p. 272.
[24] A. P. d'Entreves, Natural Law: An Introduction to Legal Philosophy (London: Hutchinson's, 1952), pp. 68-69.
[25] Robert Folz, "Le Monde Germanique," in Rene Grousset and Emile G. Leonard, eds., Histoire Universelle (Paris: Gallimard, 1957), II, 680.
[26] Asoka, the Indian Emperor of the third century B. C., conquered an empire extending from Bengal to Afghanistan, but after a particularly bloody battle he embraced Buddhism and non-violence. His empire collapsed after his rule, torn into pieces by contending pretenders.
[27] For studies on peer group influence in U. S. schools see, for example, Natalie Rogoff, "Local Social Structure and Educational Selection," in A. H. Halsey et al., eds., Education, Economy and Society (New York: Free Press, 1961), pp. 241-251; Philip E. Jacob, Changing Values in College: An Exploratory Study of the Impact of College Teaching (New York: Harper & Row, 1957) and Paul R. Abramson, Generational Change in American Polities (Lexington, Mass.: Lexington Books, 1975).
[28] Oscar Theodore Barck, Jr. and Nelson Manfred Blake, Since 2900 (New York: Macmillan, 1965), p. 356.
[29] At first, as either a sincere belief or lip service to the prevailing religious order, the rational thinkers paid tribute to Christian dogma. For example, although Descartes' methodic doubt and logical deduction -- his Cogito, ergo sum -- was a direct challenge to the Augustinian pre-rational belief, a look at the full title of his meditations reveals the care that Descartes took to try to obtain the church's favor for his philosophy. It read: Méditations sur la philosophie première, dans lesquelles sont démontrées l'existence de Dieu et la distinction de l 'âme et du corps. (This was the title of the work as it appeared in Amsterdam in 1642; another edition which had been published in 1641 in Paris had a slightly different title.) A passage in a letter Descartes wrote in April, 1634, from Amsterdam to Father Mersenne -- a literary pole of attraction who served as an intellectual clearing house in Descartes' time -- shows Descartes' concern for the views of the church. It goes: "You know, undoubtedly, that Galileo has been taken in, of late, by the Inquisitors of Faith, and that his opinion concerning the movement of the earth has been condemned as heretic. Now, I must tell you that all the things I was explaining in my treatise, among which was also this opinion on the movement of the earth, depended so much one on another, that is enough to know one of them false, to know that all the reasons I have used have no force; and while I think that they are based on very solid, and very evident demonstrations, nevertheless, for nothing in the world would I defend them against the authority of the church."
[30] Helvétius was only one of the Philosophes (the encyclopedists) who dominated the French intellectual scene of the mid-eighteenth century and greatly influenced the European philosophic world. The reasonable doubts of the encyclopedists about the supernatural were of different degrees. Voltaire (1694-1778), prominent among them, although against the institutionalized church, believed that if there were no god, man would have had to invent one. But the product of these great men, the Encyclopedie, which was completed in 28 volumes in 1772, was markedly anti-religious.
[31] See notably his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1799).
[32] An early exponent of modern materialism was La Mettrie, who in his L'Homme Machine (1748) rejected the Cartesian duality of body and soul and developed the concept of one substance, namely matter -- matter possessing the attributes of motion.
[33] In many ways the Leibnitzian "Monads," the Kantian "Ideal of rational completeness" and "Noumena," and the Hegelian "Idea" were attempts at filling the vacuum left by the absence of the Christian god. Ludwig Feuerbach pointed out this fact, as far as the Hegelian "Idea" was concerned, as early as 1843.
[34] David Hume, "Of Parties in General," Essays, Part I, viii, and "Of the Coalition of Parties," ibid., Part II, xiv. See also his "That Politics May Be Reduced to a Science," ibid., Part I, iii (1741-1742).
[35] At one end of the scale group association may exist for a specific functional goal. But it may envelop its interests in valuational premises. For example, the American Rifle Association's lobby in Washington, which safeguards the interests of the industry, claims inspiration from Article II of the Bill of Rights. At the other end of the scale a group with few outwardly functional and material interests may declare the goal of promoting a given value but actually be defending certain underlying interests. The Daughters of the American Revolution is a case in point.
[36] Maurice Duverger, Party Politics and Pressure Groups: A Comparative Introduction (New York: Crowell, 1972); Kay Lawson, The Comparative Study of Political Parties (New York: St. Martin's, 1976); and Giovanni Sartori, Parties and Party Systems (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1976).
[37] See McLuhan, Understanding Media. For his critics, see Sidney Walter Finkelstein, Sense and Nonsense of McLuhan (New York: International Publishers, 1968); and Raymond B. Rosenthal, ed., McLuhan, Pro and Can (New York: Funk and Wagnalls, 1968).
[38] For an account of the Kennedy-Nixon debates and other instances, see notably Bernard Rubin, Political Television (Belmont, Cal.: Wadsworth, 1967).
[39]
Reported by Ota
Thomas
Reynolds, "American Public Address and the Mass Media," in J. Jeffery
Auer, ed., The Rhetoric of Our Times
(New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1969), p. 173.
[40] For some data on this phenomenon and other points discussed here, see Key, Public Opinion, pp. 346 ff.
[41] Patricia Blake, "Freedom and Control in Literature, 1962-63," in Alexander Dallin and Alan F. Westin, eds., Politics in the Soviet Union (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1966), p. 167. See also Peter Viereck, "The Mob Within the Heart," Tri-Quarterly, Spring 1965, pp. 7-43.
[42] Yevgeny Yevtushenko, the Soviet poet, read his poem "Babi Yar" attacking anti-Semitism in the Soviet Union at a meeting with Khrushchev in 1963 in the Kremlin.
[43] Robert Horton, "The Economic Squeeze on Mass TV" The Reporter, 28 April 1960, pp. 14-20. See Key, Public Opinion, pp. 370-405, for data and insight on the financing and control of the mass media; and Frank Mankiewicz and Joel Swerdlow, Remote Control: Television and the Manipulation of American Life (New York: Times Books, 1978).
[44] Bertrand de Jouvenel shows that the values of big business, interested in material profit, are in contradiction to the aesthetic and literary values of creative artists. Bertrand de Jouvenel, "The Treatment of Capitalism by Continental Historians," in F. A. Hayek, ed., Capitalism and the Historians (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1954), pp. 93-i23.
[45] See notably Theodore E. Kruglak, The Foreign Correspondents: A Study of the Men and Women Reporting for the American Information Media in Western Europe (Geneva: E. Droz, 1955), pp. 100-102.
[46] On mediocrity of taste of the mass audience see Bernard C. Hennessy, Public Opinion, 2nd ed. (Belmont, Cal.: Wadsworth, 1970), pp. 319 ff.
[47] Key, Public Opinion, pp. 396 ff.
[48] Nicholas Johnson, "The Media Barons and the Public Interest--An FCC Commissioner's Warning," The Atlantic, June 1968, pp. 43-51.
[49] As did, for example, WMCA radio station in New York by being the first to endorse a presidential candidate (John F. Kennedy in 1960). See Calvin B. T. Lee, One Man, One Vote (New York: Scribner's, 1967), for a discussion of WMCA's involvement in the reapportionment case WMCA v. Lomenzo.
[50] Robert F. Kennedy in his Thirteen Days wrote of the "great impression" Tuchman's novel made on President John F. Kennedy and how it influenced his decision during the Cuban missile crisis. Robert F. Kennedy, Thirteen Days (New York: Norton, 1969), pp. 62 and 127.
[51] Daniel Lerner, "Toward a Communication Theory of Modernization: A Set of Considerations," in Lucian W. Pye, ed., Communications and Political Development (Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1963), p. 345.
[52] Steven R. Brown, "Political Literature and Response of the Reader: Experimental Studies of Interpretation, Imagery, and Criticism," APSR, 71: 567-584 (1977).
[53] See Paul Lazarsfeld, Bernard Berelson and Hazel Gaudet, The People's Choice (New York: Duell, Sloan and Pierce, 1944), notably Ch. 16, cited in Key, Public Opinion, p. 359.
[54] See, for example, Robert E. Lane, "Fathers and Sons: Foundations of Political Belief," American Sociological Review, 24:502-511 (1959); Robert F. Winch, Identification and Its Familial Determinants (Indianapolis: BobbsMerrill, 1962); James C. Davies, "The Family's Role in Political Socialization," Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 161: 11-19 (1965).
[55] A, G. Kharchev, "On Some Results of a Study of Motives for Marriage," Soviet Review, Summer 1964, pp. 3-13.
[56] Peer identification includes other variables than those based on the value-forming agencies. See our later discussion of reference groups in Chapter Nine. On the use of the peer group as a value-forming agency, see Bronfenbrenner's observation of the efforts in the Soviet Union to utilize the peer group for socializing the child. Urie Bronfenbrenner, "Response to Pressure from Peers Versus Adults Among Soviet and American School Children," International Journal of Psychology, 2:199-207 (1967).
[57] See Campbell, Gurin and Miller, The Voter Decides, p. 99.